THE DESIRE FOR DESIRE
- Can Psychoanalysis Speak About? -
_______________________________________________
Abstract/Introduction
In this paper I seek to raise some questions concerning the status
of psychoanalysis as a theory. I propose a reading of Lacan’s enigmatic 'graph
of desire' as articulated in Seminar VI and in his canonical essay The Subversion of the Subject, using it
as a didactic tool towards unraveling the structure of desire. I show how this
graph articulates Lacan's reading of the Freudian Oedipal-myth, the castration
complex, and his structuralist-inspired departure from psychological and
traditionally philosophical schemas of the subject. In this regard, I propose
to read Lacan's account of the unconscious as articulated in the order of the
signifier as attacking both empirical conceptions of the subject, epistemological
accounts of knowledge and desire, and ontological conceptions of objectivity.
I begin by presenting how Lacan’s subject
of desire articulates two asymmetrical trajectories: that of the subject of the
unconscious, and that of the signifying chain. I briefly explain how Lacan deflates
the ontological-epistemological valence of the contents of thought, by
supplanting the structuralist relation of suture
to and traversal between signifiers
for the representationalist relation of reference
between words and things, using the graph as my didactic anchor. The basic
result I wish to highlight is how every individuated being or agent, every
particularity open for thought, is made relative to the order of language, and
so that the latter admits of no exteriority subject to philosophical seizure.
Such an account illustrates the subordination of all objective individuation to
the traversal of the subject of the unconscious through the meaning-endowing defiles
of the signifier, where the imago
formed during the mirror-stage become fixed onto the symbolic order, wherein
the epistemological and psychological illusions of subjects qua self-subsistent individual of
knowledge emerge, as well as the corresponding self-subsistent other or object, nesting the ontological illusion
of a qualitatively robust conception of being. In the second section I show how
psychoanalysis is forced into a methodological quandary concerning its capacity
to articulate not just a clinical practice, but propose a series of claims
about a presumed structure. I consider some of Lacan's proposed answers to this
quandary through his account of the Real, and suggest that they force him into
a pragmatic contradiction. This is due to the inability to disambiguate between the Real as pure practice or act, and
the Real as a pure matheme or
inscription, void of meaning.
(a) The Oedipus Complex and the Imaginary -
A Mythical Prelude
Crossbreeding
the structuralist avowal of the primacy of the signifier with the Freudian
account of the unconscious, Lacan proposes to articulate a theory of subjective
desire around the singular idea that “the unconscious is structured like a
language”[1].
To understand this enigmatic formula we must assess how Lacan re-constructs the
Freudian Oedipal myth of paternal prohibition, in order to conceive of the
subject as fundamentally affected by the idea of a primordial loss; an ideal
unity which is simultaneously the basis of what the subject identifies itself
as, as well as an impossible ideality that remains forever alienated from the
subject which hosts the desire. This decentered (mis)identification of the
subject with an-other, signals that the identity of being is directly
correlative to a certain insufficiency, or a lack that makes one not yet fully
coincide with the ideality thus projected. It is insofar as the subject cannot
fully coincide with its projected identity that generates the structural
repetition of desire around an impossible object-cause (which Lacan famously
calls objet petit a). But because the
conscious identification of a determinate thing/one desired can never annul the
gap between the subject and the object, the 'Real' object of desire is rather
perpetually displacing, non-self identical object that can never be attained.
The impossible object is thus that which would interrupt the endless
circulation of desire around a concrete 'being', and rather is that which
subtracts itself from every explicit intending. The subject is thus that which
can never coincide with the individual that it identifies itself with, and the
Real object is that which can never coincide with the explicit being that it
identifies as the object of the desire. This seemingly paradoxical congruence
between the subject and the real object on the one hand, and the individual and
the being of imaginary-symbolic objectivity, and desire as the structure that
generates this insurmountable gap, is what we set ourselves to explore for the
rest of this section.
In Seminar VI, and later in The Subversion of the Subject (1967) Lacan finally proposes a series of
graphs which articulate the progressive unfolding of the subject of desire, in
its diachronic and synchronic development, tying together the general iterative
structure of the subject of desire with the developmental account of the organism.
In what follows I propose to assess this
articulation in the task of showing how the psychoanalytic account of desire is
meant to undermine the ontological-epistemological phantasy that reifies
imaginary-symbolic signifiers ("being", "knowledge",
"God"...) on the condition of excluding desire from being given its
proper due. I will suggest towards the end why this deflationary strategy
becomes problematic when assessing the status of psychoanalysis as a theory, and not just a practice. My general contention, will be
to suggest that the Lacanian reworking of intentionality, deflating the
relation of reference between words and things, creates problems when
attempting to disambiguate between the theory of desire that psychoanalysis is supposed to be, and another
manifestation of desire itself. In other words, I propose to show that
conflating the relation between the signifier and the signified, flattening the
latter into the former, creates difficulties when understanding how
psychoanalysis relates to its subject matter. But before we tentatively comment
on these larger consequences of the Lacanian project, some preliminaries are
well in order.
As is well known, at the core of the
Lacanian account of the development of the subject, is the attempt to trace how
the imaginary figurations and objectual identifications that the infant
generates between six and eighteen months of age (the so called ‘mirror-stage’[2]) constitute
a libidinal economy. I use this term
somewhat liberally to mean simply that during this stage the fundamental
structure of the subject as a subject of
desire is first articulated. For the purposes at hand, I shall not concern
myself with retelling the details of the Lacanian version of the Oedipal Myth,
which has been done in detail elsewhere[3]. What
I wish to focus on is on what I take to be the core of the account in tracing
how the images that the subject gathers and builds an identity from supports
desire by being correlated to the symbolic or language, i.e. how the subject
enters the "defiles through the signifier" within which the subject
will circulate around the (impossible) object of desire.
It is this iterative structure of desire which
is prefigured and developmentally accounted for in the Oedipal Myth. The latter
shows how the Paternal Law, which is externally imposed as a decentered
Otherness, institutes itself by enacting what we might call, following Zizek, symbolic castration. By the latter I
mean the following: in entering the order of language the self-alienating and
self-constituting split between the subject and its imaginary identifications is
relative to how language prescribes and incorporates the subject, in what Lacan
calls a 'chain of signifiers'. We shall attempt to explain this admittedly
obscure formulation below, but the basic idea is that who the subject thinks it is or should
be, its placing, so to speak, is
determined on the basis of a language that he acquires by external conditioning
as it were, and never immediately or transparently. It is this self-alienation that
articulates the inaugural phantasy of
a self-identical subject, experienced as an injunction to become
equal-to-itself, since what it lacks is precisely that which will presumably
restitute its being as a whole. In other words, the self-alienation of the
subject founds the notion of a subject as
being ontologically consistent to itself, thereby veiling the
(unbridgeable) gap between its immediate (non)-being and its imaginary-symbolic
figurations. Seeing itself outside of
itself, the subject operates according to that oft-quoted motto from
Rimbaud which Lacan was so fond of repeating during the early years of his
teaching: "je est un autre".
Because self-relation and self-constitution is paradoxically grounded in this
moment of self-alienation, it is both the moment of narcissism and that of absolute
estrangement: "One can sense, one can pick up that narcissism is involved
somewhere, and that this narcissism is involved at this moment of the Oedipus
complex." (S6, L6, pp. 92) Because the self emerges as a result of its
paradoxical attempt to become equal to an other, that is, insofar as it
experiences itself as lacking, desire
chases after a 'phantasmatic' image-symbol outside of itself. Or rather, more
precisely, the 'outside' is a function of a subject that by virtue of desiring
is split between the object it identifies itself with, and the void which
subtracts from every such identification. The structure of desire is that of a
'phantasy', a chasing after ghosts that promise to dissolve as soon as one
pretends to occupy their place.
This entails that the purported unity and
emergence of what Freud called the "perception-consciousness system"
that characterizes thinking beings is to be explained by placing it in contrast
to a notion of subjectivity that is recalcitrant with that of the ego qua decentered other. Consciousness
is of the order of the ego, since it thinks that it is the imaginary projection
of itself outside of itself that does the thinking. But Lacan's point is
precisely that the desiring is never such an external, objective pole, i.e. it thinks where it is not. This marks
accordingly the foreclosure of all attempts to think of the subject of the
unconscious as topic for "empirical"
investigation. Through the re-elaboration of the Oedipal Myth, Lacan thus aims
to show how the preponderance of those images gathered during the mirror-stage,
and the severing wound enacted by the subject’s violent insertion into the
symbolic order of language, underwrite the entire field of objective
identifications, projections, and phantasmatic hallucinations-illusions that
desire intends towards. It entails, in short, a Gestalt, conditioning the entire field of the visible world; the
individuated world of things and persons actually presupposes the structure of the subject of desire. That is,
insofar as the objectivity correlative to a subject is a function of how the
latter becomes self-alienated and constituted by virtue of desiring. Lacan
writes: "Indeed, for the imagos—whose
veiled faces it is our privilege to see in outline in our daily experience and
in the penumbra of symbolic efficacity—the mirror–image would seem to be the
threshold of the visible world, if we go by the mirror disposition that the
imago of one's own body presents in hallucinations or dreams, whether it
concerns its individual features, or even its infirmities, or its
object–projections; or if we observe the role of the mirror apparatus in the
appearances of the double, in which psychical realities, however heterogeneous,
are manifested." (E: pp. 3)
What
is interesting about the formulation above is how it effectuates a
commensuration between the images projected from the perspective of the subject's
alienation, and the 'visible world' of things. It serves simultaneously thus as
the germinal point of entry for both the epistemological
myth of the consistency of a fully consistent subject or self, as well
as for the ontological myth of a
fully consistent object or other; that is, for both philosophy and
(ego) psychology. It is crucial to
notice how the imaginary serves to create a bridge between the ‘inner world’ of
the subject (Innenwelt) and the
objective externalized world of the visible (Umwelt), around the development of self-recognition and bodily-identification[4]. In
other words, the subject-object dichotomy, from which both philosophy and
psychology depart, begins in the infant's (mis)identification and de-centering:
the idea that one's being lacks any
unified substantiality or 'selfhood' (the pure membra disjecta) emerges as a result of the identification with a
subsistent image. Being is a house of mirrors. The organic insufficiency or lack which fuels desire is but the obverse
of ideal unity, or as Lacan puts it:
"the mirror stage is the drama whose internal thrust is precipitated from
helplessness to anticipation." (E, pp. 4)
This means that the "threshold
of visible externality" that structures the world of being results from the
form-producing trajectory of subjective development. The deception is thus
twofold: the subject comes to believe that it is equal to its decentered other,
and in doing so it also believes that it is endowed with an ontologically
consistent unity. As Lorenzo Chiesa puts it: "The ego not only, as it
were, "finds itself" at the place of the other (the first
misrecognition: the ego is alienated) but also provides the subject with a
deceptive impression of unity (the second and most fundamental misrecognition:
the ego does not recognize itself as alienated). According to Lacan, it is the
ego that makes me accept as true that I am myself and that the other is the
other." (Chiesa, 2009, pp. 16)
What Chiesa insists upon here is
that if we are to take Lacan's logic to its extreme, then it's not simply that
the subject misidentifies itself with an image different from that of others.
Rather, it is precisely my identification with an other, with a decentered
image, that allows for the misidentification of the subject with it-self, that is, with what Lacan calls the
ego. In other words, it is my primary
identification with an image that locates a gap between the reality of the subject as the agent of thought and as an
object of thought, i.e. in
identifying itself with the mirror-image, the subject objectifies itself as an ideal ego, which entails that the
objectual is constitutively ideal or imaginary. This seems to be the meaning
behind the cryptic statement from Lacan that the ego, in its narcissistic
stupor, constitutes "a vital dehiscence that is constitutive of
man" (E, pp. 4)
The next step, for us, is to explain how
these imaginary functions are at the same time mediated by the cultural order
of language. The symbolic brings about a ‘castrating function’ which throws the
subject out of joint with its imaginary unity, and sets off the unending,
impossible quest for its recuperation. Lacan
refers to the order of language as the (big) Other, which signals that it
constitutes a decentered place of
identification, like the other of the
imaginary, but also that it constitutes an impersonal
field constituted by the community into which one is inserted[5].
By tethering the subject of the unconscious to the symbolic Lacan means to say
that language is in a sense a transcendent authority that ordains and issues
the injunctions before which desire sets itself. Desire is the desire of the Other precisely insofar as it is
mediated by an order of language which pre-exists and determines its
organization[6]. Or, put
differently, one never desires immediately, but only through particular
prescriptions and mediations issued from the impersonal order of language, on
whose basis the subject intends towards anything whatsoever, in the phantasy
for self-realization. Chiesa explains that "...the specular, alienating
identification of the subject with the imaginary other necessarily presupposes
an earlier, original - and perpetual- alienation in the Other qua language." (Chiesa, 2009, pp.
25)
The logical priority of the symbolic
entails both that the self-identification of the subject with the imago occurs as the subject is inserted
into language, and that the identification of others as others (both individuals and objects, persons and things) is
conditioned by the linguistic order of the signifier, i.e. individuation is a
function of language, and this articulates both the epistemic-psychological
dimensions of self-understanding, as well as the ontological dimensions of
understanding others and the world. Castration means at this juncture that a
gap persists not just between the imaginary ideal
ego and the subject, but between the latter and the Ego-Ideal of symbolic-imaginary prescriptions. The latter expresses
the fact that, traversed by language, the ideality of the imaginary is also an
impossible archetypical form which localized the subject's libidinal
orientation. This structure is simultaneously that which provides thus the
condition for consciousness as consciousness of something, and that which eludes the explicit 'aboutness' of
such conscious intentionality, insofar as the phantasy of reconstitution
remains precisely ideal, both an
imaginary form and a symbolic injunction. Castration thus means that language
enjoins the subject to rejoin, entailing its being as disjointed, that is, as
directed towards an external pole which it can never become equal to: ($ <> a).
It
is insofar that the subject constitutes its unconscious as a result of this
alienating operation of 'symbolic castration' that it is not a mere myth to be allotted to the inventions of
philosophers and psychologists alike: “what is not a myth, although Freud
formulated it just as early on as he formulated the Oedipus myth, is the
castration complex” (E; Pg. 695). This forms a necessary corrective the myths
of subjective intentionality that located desire at the level of explicit
consciousness, since for them "... it seemed that consciousness was
inherent to what the subject had to say qua signification" (SV, pp. 105).
But if the unconscious is structured like a language, then the intentionality
of unconscious desire is also of the order of the signifier. Redoubling our
earlier distinction between individual ego and subject, at the level of the
symbolic we can map the distinction between the subject of the statement and the subject of enunciation. The former is expressly formulated in
speech or writing, individuated by the inclusion into the symbolic order and grammatically
objectivated within the sequences of signifiers and sentences that structure
discourse. One therefore becomes constituted as the subject who speaks after the act of speech is taken
to have been meaningfully
articulated, i.e. identity emerges in a retroactive assignment of meaning to
the sequentially deployed utterance of the subject who speaks. The subject of the enunciation, on the other
hand, is the slippery index for the
subject of the unconscious, which
remains forever subtracted and incomplete from desire’s imaginary-symbolic
operations, and from the statement. It is utterly meaningless, barren, bereft,
barred, and void of quality. As Lacan
puts it, the subject is split and never present to itself "...by virtue of being a subject only
insofar as it speaks" (E, pp. 269). Or, in his startling reversal of
Descartes: "I think where I am not, therefore I am where I do not
think", i.e. the unconscious thinks and intends subtracted from the explicit forms making the Ego-Ideal. (Ibid, pp.
166)
However,
the most important point we must underline here is that the subject of
enunciation does not stand to the subject of the statement as signified stands
to signifier, or represented to representing. Lacan is adamant to insist in
that the individuating function of the big Other is not merely
representationalist in the sense that it 'tracks down things' through words or
signs; it refuses to be ontologised or positivized. This constitutes the kernel
of Lacan's flattening of the Saussurian relation of signification as holding between signs and things, to one where
signification obtains between signifiers exclusively: "The signifier
doesn't just provide an envelope, a receptacle for signification. It polarizes
it, it structures it, and brings it into existence." (S3, pp. 224) Or yet
again: "The signifier is a sign that doesn't refer to any object... It is
a sign which refers to another sign, which is as such structured to signify the
absence of another sign, in other words, to be opposed to it in a couple."
(Ibid, pp. 167) As a result, both subject and object are delivered to a
structure of signification, void of any ontological status, and to relations
between signifiers, void of epistemological status.
What I
would like to suggest eventually is that it is not only the subject of the
unconscious which becomes delivered from the empirical pretences of
ego-psychology or transcendental philosophy into the order of language, but
also the intended objects of consciousness which become delivered from the
empirical pretences of metaphysicians and ontologists to the delirium of the
signifier. As a result, the unconscious is crucially neither the subject, nor
an object; it has no determinate ontological or epistemic status: "...what
still becomes apparent to anyone in analysis who spends some time observing
what truly belongs to the order of the unconscious, is that it is neither being,
nor non-being, but the unrealized." (SXI, pp 30) As a result, the
disjunction between psychoanalysis and philosophy is meant to be total since
"the gap of the unconscious seems to be pre-ontological... it does not
lend itself to ontology" (Ibid. 29) Does this leave open that something
like the 'being of the world' may nonetheless subsist in the order of consciousness, along its much vaunted
intentionality? For if indeed, as Lacan puts it, "the Freudian world isn't
a world of things, it isn't a world of being, it is a world of desire as
such", then couldn't the relation of knowing
in which things, and not just words, come into mind, be said to subsist at some
level? (S2, pp. 222)
I
wish to defer this question for the moment, but to make a few preliminaries in
the way. My preliminary contention is that insofar as the relation between
words and things is flattened to the relation between signifiers, ontology
might be said to subsist trivially at the price of subordinating it to the
structure of desire. This weakens the ontological valence of 'beings' or
'being' to merely ideal poles for the phantasies of philosophers, which does
not so much deny ontology as much as
it suspends its purported prerogative
when securing our access to the "world of being", understood as that
of a mind independent reality. It thereby flattens the philosophical pretence
of gaining traction before the world to the uniform register of an unconscious
desire which, like every other, is supported in nothing else than in the signifying
chain and its metonymic inscriptions. Yet this answer seems to preemptively
defang ontology from its capacity to prey on the world, after which its
peculiarity becomes a matter of organization at the level of signifier. In this
regard, Badiou's reading of Lacan as an anti-philosopher stresses how, once
demoted to one more discursive practice among others, psychoanalysis would
carry out "a deposing of the category of philosophy to constitute itself
as theory... philosophy is an act, of which the fabulations about 'truth' are
the clothing, the propaganda, the lies." (Badiou, 2010, pp 75) I will
later suggest why it is not clear, however, that psychoanalysis can legitimize
itself as a theory without reactivating the kinds of distinctions it takes to be
proper of philosophico-scientific discourse, and will proceed to ask what
consequences follow for the formal
coherence of psychoanalysis, as well as for its purported content. That is to say, we shall ask how psychoanalysis relates to
its subject matter.
(b) The Castration Complex, the Loop of Desire
and the Symbolic
If desire is articulated within the order of
the signifier, then the symptom of the unconscious phantasy must be tethered to
the imaginary-symbolic. The subject of the enunciation thus becomes readable
and visible only within the symptomatic-metonymic elements deployed in the
signifying chain, in an “...extinction that is still glowing and an opening
that stumbles, I can come into being by disappearing from my statement"
(E; Pg. 678). Thus, the psychoanalytic operation towards the unconscious is
not one of digging for a pre-linguistic positive content hidden behind the
signifying chain, which would constitute the ‘real subject’ after sublating and
shedding off its feeble illusions. More subtly, it attempts to find within the signifying chain itself those
symptomatic anomalies and ruptures which locate the subject’s unconsciously
articulated desire, i.e. its metonymic points of torsion and articulation. Thus
Lacan emphasizes the “…the radical role of metaphor and metonymy, substitution
and combination of signifiers in synchronic and diachronic dimensions"
(Ibid). Whereas the subject of knowledge
is an illusion, the subject of the unconscious
is not merely a myth: "the subject [of knowledge] correlative to the
object, the subject around whom turns the eternal question of idealism, and who
is himself an ideal subject...he is only supposed." (S6, L2, pp. 18). I
will later suggest that the problematic of idealism is not entirely done away with
by deflating the valence of knowledge. For now, let us see how Lacan maps the
structure of the unconscious subject across the signifying chain[7]:
The graph transparently presents two asymmetrical but synchronous trajectories: the parabola of the subject of enunciation (also called the subject of intention), and the signifying chain wherein the grammatical subject of the statement becomes expressed. At the base of both trajectories, we see the symbol ∆, which stands for the imaginary mythical subject of need, i.e. the posited notion of the child before the mirror-stage and the castration complex. It is interesting to note that since Lacan insists that individuation and selfhood proceeds from traversing the imaginary-symbolic orders, this pre-linguistic being can only be said to exist as a 'myth', for the developmental story to get off the ground. Whether this move is theoretically legitimate is a delicate point, which I believe requires that we confront some general aspects of Lacan's theory of individuation, which I do in the next section fully. For now, let us simply grant that this mythical subject is supposed to function as a 'base' in the trajectory of both lines.
Immediately above the trajectory of the
subject of the enunciation we see the formation of the ‘spectral image’ or ideal ego, i(o), which corresponds to
the imaginary other objectified during the 'mirror-image'. At the very end of
this trajectory, we can see how this primitive ideality consolidates the Ego-Ideal, i.e. the prescribed identity
issued from the intersection of the imaginary and the symbolic that addresses the statement to the desire of the other, within the order of language
(I(O)). Thus Lacan claims that "every phantasy is articulated in terms of
the subject speaking to the imaginary other." (SVI, L2, pp. 12) The
intersection at (O) designates the "puncturing" insertion of the
subject into the symbolic order (point de
caption), the “big Other” of language from which there is a retroactive
determination of the meaning of the signifying chain which composes statements. As such, the Otherness of
language fixes the presumed identity of the speaking subject of the statement which
constitutes an identity separated from the amorphousness of “the Voice”, the
remainder at the end of this trajectory: "what he [the subject] is
questioning himself about is far from being the response, it is the
questioning;. It is effectively "what is this signifier of the Other in
me?" (S6; L1; pp. 7).
This
dual function of the (O) appears clearer once we understand that entering the
symbolic proper entails that language structures one's capacities to act (the
Law), as well as setting a standard for what is expected of the subject to
become. This is why, strictly speaking, desire can only be of the Other, since it is always mediated and fixed retroactively
in a puncturing carried out by the subject.
It is to this meaning-endowing Other that speech is directed: “is what
may be called the punctuation, in which signification ends as a finished
product.” (E; Pg 682)
The
insertion of the unconscious into the symbolic order does never, so to speak ,
'reach out' onto things: "...the sign does not take its value with respect
to a third thing that it represents, but it takes on its value with respect to
another signifier which it is not." (Ibid; pp. 7) This is crucial, since
what closes the statement is not finally some stable identification with a
‘real object’ of ostentation, as in Kripke’s theory of rigid designation, but
only a transient signifier to which it tethers its imaginary semblances and
figurations. Thus we have a retroactive determination from the linear vector of
the signifying chain which goes from s(O) - (O), back into s(O), marking where
meaning is assigned only after the subject indexes the closure of the statement[8]: “The
subject's submission to the signifier, which occurs in the circuit that goes
from s(O) to O and back
from O to s(O), is truly a circle, inasmuch as the assertion that is
established in it—being unable to close on anything but its own scansion, in
other words, failing an act in which it would find its certainty—refers back
only to its own anticipation in the composition of the signifies which is in
itself meaningless insignificante”
(Ibid; Pg 683). The “treasure
trove of signifiers” that organizes language forms a circular motion, where the
signifying chain is punctured by the subject’s deliverance to the symbolic so
as to constitute itself, while the latter retroactively fixes the meaning of
the entire statement that makes it a statement of a subject. The identity of the subject of the statement it thus
constituted retroactively, insofar as an otherwise barren chain of signifiers
is punctured by the subject. This clarifies
how desire needs to be objectivated and fixated in the external Otherness of
language by becoming stapled to a (transient) signifier to stand for an object
to endow with meaning the statement
and so for the subject to allow for the possibility of recognition. The point
is that this endless pursuit for meaning and identity masks the void of
desire's repetition, and the latter's perpetual displacement across the
signifying chain. The big Other's insatiable demand enroots the subject in
desire as it wrests it from the bare need of the mythical, pre-linguistic
subject: “Desire begins to take shape in the margin in which the demand rips
away from need… A margin which, as linear as it may be, allows its vertiginous
character to appear… it is this whimsy that introduces the phantom of
Omnipotence- not of the subject, but of the Other in which the subject’s demand
is instantiated.” (Ibid; 689)
This also
explains Lacan’s famous proto-Hegelian claim alluded to earlier that “man’s
desire is the Other’s desire… it is qua
Other that man desires.” (Ibid) In other words, desire is always fixed and
objectivated by anchoring the imaginary field of spectral images through the
castrating externality of language, which marks for the subject a constitutive
loss and therefore is experienced as an imperative for reconstitution and
recognition. The desire of the subject
will fix itself thus in the form of a demand
from the Other’s desire, from the big Other which closes the signifying chain
by blessing it with the seal of meaning: "what does the Other want from me?" (Ibid, 690-691) It is within the order of the signifier and to a signifier that desire is directed,
and not outside of it towards a thing or being. This is what Lacan describes as
"...man's capture in the components of the signifying chain." (Ibid,
pp. 6) We must conclude, therefore, that language is, like Heidegger surmised,
the house of being. But the house of language is also a house of mirrors, and one
with no windows.
The
final part of the parabola illustrates how, having traversed the defiles
through the signifier, the conjunction of the symbolic and the imaginary once
the subject has been affected by symbolic castration, projecting his ideal
unity in the form of the Ego-Ideal: I(O). That is, the self-image constituted
by the interpellation of the Other’s desire. The space of the Ego-Ideal is thus
the end of the trajectory of the subject of the enunciation in coincidence to
how the amorphous Voice is the end of the subject of the statement. Once again,
there is a retroactive effectuation in order, where the subject determines not
just the object which will have been
meant in the statement, but also the subject “he will have been” (Ibid): “This trajectory which ends in the [ego-ideal]
is a retroversion effect by which the subject, at each stage, becomes what he
was (to be) [etait] before that, and "he will have been" is
only announced in the future perfect tense.” [E; Pg. 684] Desire effectuates
both the metonymic insertion of being in the subject, and that of the subject
in being; it alienates the subject into the other, while the object of desire,
ever impossible, becomes like the subject in failing to become a stable
identity itself: "Desire is the metonymy of being in the subject; the
phallus [qua object of desire] is the metonymy of the subject in being."
(SVI, L1, pp. 15)
At the base of the parabolic trajectory,
disconnected from the subject of need and the sequence of the movement, we have
the barred-subject $, which stands
for the formal void of a severed ground. This is a sign that is not part of the
statement, but rather a disjoined
signifier for the unconscious. Since there is no substantive content proper to
the barred subject, no statement which predicates its 'proper being', Lacan
consistently claims that there is no Other of the Other: that there is no
subject to be captured ‘outside’ of the Otherness of language or, what amounts
to the same, that “…there is no metalanguage.” (E, 688) Put differently, one
never "reaches out" outside of language, either directly onto an
other subject, or, what amounts to the same, to being as an object, since
"...what characterizes the demand is not just that it is a relationship of
a subject to another subject [or between a subject and an object], it is that
this relationship is made through the mediation of language, through the
mediation of a system of signifiers." (SVI, L3, pp. 27) The movement of
the Real occurs by and through the order of the signifier, not as a foreign
transcendence. The primitive individuation of the imaginary realm, which as we
saw constitutes the entire field of the visible, traverses the order of the
signifier constituting the vain phantasy to regain the impossible object which
would endow its void with an integral consistency.
(c) The Cunning of Being or the Being of
Cunning?
If the subject of the unconscious is
indeed structured like a language, and desire is nothing but the articulation
between signifiers, then the much vaunted Freudian 'world of desire' is an
ideal world populated by phantasms; not a world as much as the height of
narcissistic alienation, the nightmare which is nothing but a dream come true.
At this point we should ask again: does this mean that even if the relation of knowing between words and things does
not hold good for the structure of the unconscious,
it might nevertheless be thinkable within the realm of consciousness?
In this stronger formulation, I
believe that our question must be answered to in the negative. For it is clear
that the "Freudian world" isn't just another world which, in dualist metaphysical spirits, would neatly
leave the innocence of the world of knowing to its own operations, untouched.
Indeed, Lacan is adamant to show not only that the world of desire is not the
world of things, but that the unconscious conditions
the operations of consciousness and seals its every pretence within the economy
of desire: "Relations between human beings are really established before
one gets to the domain of consciousness. It is desire which achieves the
primitive structuration of the human world, desire as unconscious." (S2,
pp. 224) More dramatically still, it's precisely desire's undermining of
consciousness that makes the explicit conscious claims to the universal of being subordinate to the
unconscious singularity of the
symptom, or as Lacan reminds us: "...don't forget that consciousness isn't
universal." (Ibid). If this is so, then the valence of the ontological
independence of the 'realm of things' could at best be an epiphenomenal
illusion, a veil under which the iterations of desire and the symptom displace
themselves in the order of the signifier. In fact, Lacan explicitly
subordinates the object of knowledge to the object of desire, and claims that
in the vector leading from the barred subject to its decentered other, the
small impossible object of desire, one finds the (illusion) of knowledge:
"$ in the presence of o and
which we call the phantasy, which in the
psychic economy represents something that you know." (Ibid, pp 214). This
is why it is, paradoxically, desire that is the metonymy of being in the subject, insofar as it is through the
self-alienating insertion into the impersonal Other of language that the
subject releases its intentionality through linguistic mediation, and not from
the realm of "Being" that offers itself 'as a gift' to immediate experience,
as in the phenomenological Myth of the Given (to use Sellars' phrase). What
philosophers reify as knowledge is in truth the knowledge of the Other, insofar
as it is attributed to the subject as individuated in the impersonal symbolic
order: ""What is it that knows?" Do we realize that it is the
Other?... as a locus in which the signifier is posited, as without which
nothing indicates to us that there is a dimension of truth anywhere, a
di-mension, the residence of what is said, of this said whose knowledge posits
the Other as locus." (SXX, pp. 96)
The philosophical questioning that
aims at knowledge is thus to be understood as the subject's depositing of his
speech within the punctuation of the symbolic, rather than the Real. The power
of the question brings us closer not to a palpitating realm behind the order of
the signifier, but only to the demand
issued from within this order; it
must subordinate its positivity to it, and find itself always-already lost in
it. For the subject, "what he is questioning himself about is far from
being the response, it is the questioning. It is effectively 'What is this
signifier of the Other in me?" (S1, L9, pp. 132). By fixating itself into the order of the
signifier, ruminating in search for the impossible lost object, the quest for
self proves, ironically, an inversion of the philosophical genealogy of thought,
a predecessor of the quest for being as such: "... the bar is the hidden
signifier, the one that the Other does not have at its disposition, and which
is precisely the one which concerns you: it is the same one that makes you
enter the game in so far as you, poor simpletons, since you were born, were
caught up in this sacred logos
business." (Ibid; L16, pp. 207). And indeed it is telling that the quest
for being should be of no concern for the psychoanalyst, but that he rather
makes of desire that which deserves to be called "the essence of
man", signaling its logical, if
not chronological, priority (S6, L1,
pp 4)[9].
However, this predicament forces Lacan
into a quandary. For if the subject of knowledge is indeed subordinate to the
unconscious, and if the relation between signifier and signified is flattened
to the chains in the former, how are we to understand what for Lacan, indeed
for psychoanalysis, must be a theory of desire? That is, how can Lacanian
psychoanalysis, in erecting its formidable conceptual structure, proclaim to give
a structured theory and not just
constitute an improvised practice,
i.e. how is it to become a discourse in which the structural features of desire
are outlined and articulated? For if there is no relation between words and
things, then what relation do the theoretical statements formulated in
psychoanalysis purportedly bear to its presumed subject matter? What is the
role of the peculiar signifier "desire"
in the economy of psychoanalysis, if there is, strictly speaking, nothing 'out
there' to be spoken of, no 'thing' populating the world which can escape the
latency of the phantasy? And similarly
for 'unconscious', 'signifier', "subject", and the entire roster of concepts that psychoanalysis deploys continuously, when claiming to
explain the generality of desire as a
structure, and not just as manifesting one more iteration of desire as a symptom, like every other.
Preemptively, one might answer that indeed
because psychoanalysis elides the referential relation it is never trying to
'reach out' onto things or to give an ontology, peeking behind the words, but
is rather consigned to survey the latent
content in which the signifying chain becomes deployed and used. Thereby, the
analyst is not a knower, claiming to
access the 'things behind the appearances', since that would performatively
contradict the purported demotion of epistemology/psychology and philosophy,
but is rather concerned with the reality of appearances only, with how they
find their place within the structure of signification as such.
But this is simply to inflect the
issue into the order of language. For if psychoanalysis is not just one more phantasy in search for its own
impossible object, then this is because what Lacan is effectively doing is not
simply speaking to us qua analysands, addressing the particularity of our (paradoxically) universal symptom, but rather
outlining the general structure of
desire. In other words, the statements issued by psychoanalysis allegedly pertain
not just to one more discourse in the same footing before desire as all others,
but must rather allow us to gain traction before desire as such. If not, then the artifice of psychoanalytic claims
would do nothing but make the signifier "desire" its very own symptom, its own localization of the
impossible object, in a hysteric attempt to wage against the organization of
the purported hegemony of philosophers and psychologists. Yet, in this case, psychoanalytic
theory thereby elides its own position of enunciation, with the nefarious
result that the discourse of the master and that of the analyst would seem to
conflate through the operations of a
kind of University discourse directed against itself. If Lacan is indeed an
anti-philosopher, it is insofar as in waging war against the ontological
phantasy, he thus nevertheless remains within its confines; where the masterdom
of the University and knowledge, indeed of being, is being subverted in the
name of the psychoanalytic theoretical statements itself. It is crucial to note
that this theoretical operation is external to the clinical practice of the
discourse of the analyst, and also that it conditions the thought of the
separation of the analyst discourse from the other three. For what could the
deliberate intent to subvert the 'dominating discourse' that symptomatically
evinces an instance of phantasy in analysis mean for someone who is addressing
the psychoanalytic community itself? From which position of enunciation could
the theoretical statements of psychoanalysis be issued from, if it is neither a
form of the presumed neutrality of objective knowledge proper to University
discourse, but neither an instance for the discourse of the analyst? What could
psychoanalysis claim to be doing if, as Lacan has repeatedly insisted, there is
no meta-language, and if "there is no Other of the Other? In other words,
for the subject of traditional philosophy, this subject subjectivises itself indefinitely.
There is not in the Other, any signifier which is able on this occasion to
answer for what I am." (Ibid; L16, pp. 206)
If the signifier that stands for the subject of the unconscious, the
psycho-biological development story of the castration complex, or the
figurations of desire in the form of graphs, are to count as theoretical at all, then it seems that
Lacan must rehabilitate the distinction between signifier and signified that he
had sworn to abjure. But in doing so, psychoanalysis would need to reactivate
the valence of knowing, indeed of the
subject of knowledge, in making the latter track down and express the structure
of desire as such. As we saw above, this is precisely what was taken to be
impossible: desire trumps knowledge, the latter is only the envelope of the
former. And indeed, if knowledge of
desire can be obtained or localized from the vantage point of psychoanalytic
theory, there seems nothing to keep the philosopher from claiming that what Lacan
is doing is effectively ontologizing desire
and thus the subject of the unconscious as the libidinal variant of the realm
of appearances, and that therefore Lacan has merely supplanted philosophy and
psychology with its own prescriptive ideational framework, apt for empirical
investigation, i.e. the realm of the unconscious that is "structured like
a language".
Indeed,
Lacan himself seems to have been aware of this crucial paradox within his
theoretical register from very early on. In what I take to be a decisive
statement, Lacan claims with regards to the conceptual status of the
psychoanalytic theoretical endeavor: "There is a fundamental ambiguity in
the use we make of the word 'desire'. Sometimes we objectify it- and we have to
do so, if only to talk about it. On the contrary sometimes we locate it
as the primitive term, in relation to any objectification." (S2, pp. 225)
This ambiguity is not trivial whatsoever. For if desire must be objectified in order to be spoken about,
in what sense is it any different than any of the other terms that philosophers
or scientists purportedly use to describe phenomena of all kinds, desire included?
How are we to understand the claim that desire is simultaneously of the order of signifier and that which conditions any
objectification whatsoever? How can a signifier stand for the barred subject $,
disjoined from the signifying chain in the Otherness of language? This
problem is particularly acute, since Lacan insists that desire cannot be ontologised. But then what is
it that psychoanalytic theory is doing when they 'objectify' desire "if
only to speak of it"? How could such an act constitute anything but an
ontological valence? Yet to claim that desire is not just a signifier, but
rather the enabling condition for
signification and objectivation, is once again to reactivate the relation
between signifier and signified, only this time in terms of desire as real
precondition for objects understood as linguistically individuated posits. This
would be to covertly ontologise desire as an Aristotelian 'first mover', as the
'ground of being', as Ineffable Being stripped even of the honor of the name.
Correspondingly, this makes utterly indeterminate how the posterior
objectification of desire in words relates to desire as a precondition for this
objectification.
At
this juncture, neither option will work: if Lacan claims that the
objectification of desire relates to the pre-objectified desire, then he has
reactivated the referential relation between signifier and signified, sign and
referent, in the dichotomy between objectual desire-for-us and unobjectifiable desire-in-itself.
This surrenders Lacan to a bizarre, libidinal paradox of Kantianism (which is
after all how Lacan always read Kant anyway). But to do that he must once again
rehabilitate not just the ontological
valence of desire as such, but the epistemological
valence of the relation between desire's objectification in language and
the depths of the desire that it bridges us to in the act of theorizing it,
that is, in the making of claims about
it. It is impossible to understand Lacan's claim that desire is a
'precondition' for its objectification unless one reenacts this philosophical
cunning of the original psychoanalytic coup against philosophy and science.
Alternatively, Lacan can say that
the objectification in question needs of no such relation, and consistently
maintain that the signifier "desire"
is, like every other, merely in relation to other signifiers, but never aiming
towards anything like an ontologically generative 'in-itself'. Thus the terms
of psychoanalysis would escape the faith of standing as signifiers for signifieds, and so avoid tacitly
playing the role of a 'meta-language'. Indeed, this is what at some point Lacan
himself seems to want to claim when he says that "Desire emerges just as
it becomes embodied in speech, it emerges with symbolism." (SII, pp. 234).
In this reading, the original ambiguity is resolved in favor of a pure
objectification of something which, strictly speaking, does not preexist the
act of objectification itself.
Nevertheless, without distinguishing
how the signifiers making up theoretical statements fulfill this role without
becoming one more instance of the University discourse, but neither falling
into the other three forms of discourse, this route ultimately undermines the
theoretical status of psychoanalysis. The purported connection to the phenomenon of desire becomes in
principle proscribed, and deprives itself of any authority when describing the
subordination of knowledge to desire in theoretical terms. For there could be no
categorical distinction between those signifiers that will play the role of
mere signifiers in their discursive operation according to the four forms, and
those of psychoanalytic theory which
may unravel their conditions of possibility, lest we return to the
philosophical vocation, or occupy the once again the position of the University
discourse by prescribing a kind of knowledge.
And yet, to attempt such a foreclosing
act, to shun the danger of the 'Great outdoors' by claiming that desire as such
is intractable to any kind of objectification, effectively undermines itself as
a gesture. This is because if psychoanalysis cannot validate itself as a
theory, neither can the structure of desire it purportedly formalizes and
describes as being 'outside all objectifying description' be used to undermine itself in relation to other theories and
discourses in general. In other words, psychoanalysis couldn't even surrender
its rights to desire without already having 'spoken that which can't be
spoken', that is, without already assuming a theoretical position claiming to
know of desire as an asymptotic horizon which forecloses all theorizing. The
result is a fundamental paradox whereby psychoanalysis ceases to be a theory
because the exigencies of desire undermine it, and where desire ceases to be
the structural phenomenon psychoanalysis describes because the latter is not a
theory[10].
Two scenarios appear possible at his
point, as the necessary correctives to psychoanalytic theory. Yet, we shall
see, that the ambiguity of desire as a term
and as a condition is ultimately
irresolvable. Lacan claimed to have superseded the pretences of philosophy but
in turn seems to be forced into the choice between a variant of transcendental
idealism and sophistry. The former scenario has itself two possibilities: a) a
kind of negative-theological epistemic understanding of the foreclosure of Real
desire as that which resists objectification and meaning, and b) a variety of
textual idealism where desire is immanent to the signifier, while admitting of
a typology of signifiers. Let us assess each of these .
First, a possible answer is to
leave it open that psychoanalysis may gain traction with respect to desire, via
the objectification of the signifier. That is, the signifier might grant
restricted access to desire as an unknowable,
unobjectifiable, but nevertheless thinkable
condition of possibility for signification (a variety of 'weak correlationism').
Under this light, Lacan's account of desire as Real precondition begins to
startlingly resemble the minimal realism of Heidegger, for whom the opaqueness
of the Earth qua unobjectifiable
being stands as necessarily refractory to the variegated structure of world,
with its populated entities and individuations at the ontic level. Real desire
would be the proto-ontological motor conditioning, ironically, the merely ontic
register of being and the symbolic investment of symptoms. The early Lacan seems
to indicate this much when he claims in a rather cryptic passage:
"Desire... is the desire for nothing namable... this desire lies at the
origin of every variety of animation. If being were only what it is there
wouldn't be room to talk about it. Being comes into existence as an exact
function of this lack." (SII, pp 223). This is the direction in which the
later Lacan, through his idea of the Real as that which resists symbolization,
seems to have succumbed, as we shall see below[11].
Alternatively, in this first re-philosophizing
scenario, the structure of desire remains epistemically accessible without
residue, but confined to the signifying order, in which case Lacan is involved
in a bizarre structuralist parody of textual idealism. Yet as we surmised
above, this cannot be done, strictly speaking, without a qualitative
distinction that vitiates the structural uniformity of the signifier. In other
words, it requires a qualitative distinction within the order of the signifier, a typology that sets those signs
which map the structure of desire from those which are merely within the
libidinal commerce of phantasy, and so those which are subordinated to the
former. Both options in this scenario rehabilitate the philosophical spooks that
Lacan took to have demoted, at the price of reactivating the possibility of a
special kind of reference or relation between signifiers, apart from the
articulation of the four discourses and with it having the status of a
'meta-language' assigned to save psychoanalytic theory from itself.
The second alternative, foreclosing the
explanatory purchase on desire, and leaving exteriority unthinkable, shuns the status of psychoanalysis as a theory and
surrenders it to a sophistic endeavor marking its internal contradiction (a
variety of strong correlationism). This is the tragedy that we surmised above,
when showing that psychoanalysis couldn't even surrender its rights to
knowledge. For in this scenario, the Lacanian edifice ends up effectively
undermining itself, rendering the conceptual endeavor it pursues into utter
incoherence, the knowledge of desire undermining its theorization, and the
theorization of desire undermining the possibility of knowledge of it[12].
As we suggested above, however, Lacan
seems to have progressively realized that he couldn't do without explaining how
a theory of desire relies on such a
conceptual envelopment, as evinced in a particularly telling passage: "[Our]
conception of the concept implies that the concept is always established in an
approach that is not unrelated to that which is imposed on us, as a form, by
infinitesimal calculus. Indeed, if the concept is modeled on an approach to the
reality that the concept has been created to apprehend, it is only by a leap a
passage to the limit, that it manages to realize itself. We are then required
to say in what respect- under what form of finite quantity, I would say- the
conceptual elaboration known as the unconscious may be carried out." (SXI:
pp. 19)
Yet
at this point, signaling both the beginning of a mathematical obsession and
that of a poetic escape, Lacan begins to opt for the first horn of the dilemma
and to surrender psychoanalysis to what appears under all lights to be a
re-philosophizing of its fundamental task, along with the valence of knowing. A
passion for the purity of formalization and the inscription, which begins the
sliding down the notion that the matheme
is closest to the Real, being sutured itself to nothing but a void. This void
that, to be sure, although not named "Being"
for Lacan, has been nothing but the proper name of Being for dialectical
philosophers for a long time. The nothingness of the Real thus becomes an
absolute abstraction, like Hegel claimed apropos
Being, which is, in itself, indistinguishable from Nothing, that is, from
non-being. The matheme becomes the
receptacle of a pure transmission, insofar as formalization subtracts the
symbol from its conceptual envelopment, prizing it free from any semblance of
meaning or intention. This is why the matheme,
indexes, for Lacan, how: "The mathematical formalization of signifierness
runs counter to meaning." (SXX, pp. 93) What formalization enables is not
a representation of desire and so of
a knowledge about the Real, but
rather an experience or 'act' with respect the Real, a possibility for transference:
"Truth cannot convince, knowledge becomes act" (Ibid; Pg. 104).
But since the matheme is closest to the Real insofar
as it formalizes while symbolizing nothing,
this Real becomes that which cannot
be positivized in a representation. The Real subtracts itself from all positive
content, it is delivered only to the pure act of transmission, the transference
of something which opens the promise for the traversal of the phantasy. Just
like the subject, there can be thus no theoretical knowledge of the Real: the
latter cannot be totalized or unified, and therefore it cannot be qualitatively
determined so as to be tractable conceptually: "If there is a notion of the real, it is extremely complex
and, because of this, incomprehensible, it cannot be comprehended in a way that
would make an All out of it."[13]
Accordingly, the object-cause of desire as a Real is thought through the
formalization of a vanishing object, non-identical to itself, always alienating
the subject from the place of enunciation. This is why the phallus, as the mask hiding
the displacement of the object, constitutes the metonymy of the subject in being: the object of desire is 'subjectivized'
insofar as it refuses to ever coincide with the phallic semblances under which
it appears or is formulated. This 'becoming subject of substance', to speak
Hegelese, is what makes the meaningless formalism 'nearest' to the Real object
and so to the unconscious desire. This object-cause of desire is then
necessarily also a "non-object" insofar as it resists the effects of
the symbolization that envelops it in contingent demands, constituting the
non-being that appears under the semblance of being: "Being on the right
path [leading from the symbolic to the Real], overall, [object a], would have
us take it for being, in the name of the following - that it is apparently
something. But it only dissolves, in the final analysis, owing to its failure,
unable, as it is, to sustain itself in approaching the real." (SXX, pp.
95)
But if this is the case, then the Real
becomes the obverse of castration, the stain of a remainder that propels desire
and before which nothing but a pure matheme,
void of referential pretence, can stand before in its formal opaqueness[14]. And
it is here that the unobjectifiable Real of the act of transference is
construed by a tacit separation from the matheme
that ordains it, evincing a division that psychoanalysis ultimately cannot resolve.
Much like for Heidegger Being qua the
unobjectifiable opaqueness of the Earth cannot be apprehended conceptually but
must be delivered to the poetic word of the thinker and the act of the artist,
the Real qua unobjectifiable
opaqueness of desire cannot be known but must be delivered to the matheme and the transference occasioned
by the analyst. As Lacan puts it: "Mathematization alone reaches a real -
and it is in that respect that it is compatible with our discourse, with
analytic discourse- a real that has nothing to do with what traditional
knowledge has served as a basis for, which is not what the latter believes it
to be- namely, reality, but rather phantasy... The Real, I will say, is the
mystery of the speaking body, the mystery of the unconscious." (SXX; pp.
131)
However, the call for the bodily act signals
also the inevitable moment of loss for explanation,
the moment in which, no longer capable of separating the thought of the Real
from the Real itself, one must surrender all theoretical pretences and en-act
the traversal itself, a clinical pilgrimage before the inflections of the
symptom through the lessons of formalization. The
discursive access to knowing-that becomes delivered to the oblique efficacy of
non-discursive know-how. This is how we should coordinate these two
seemingly disparate statements from Lacan: "There is some rapport of being
that cannot be known" (SXX, pp. 119, TM), and "If analysis rests on a
presumption, it is that knowledge about [subjective] truth can be constituted
on the basis of its experience" (Ibid, pp. 91). The impossibility of a
knowledge of being is but the obverse
of the possibility of knowing how to speak
in bringing about the transference. Or as Badiou formulates it: "The paradoxical
position of Lacan concerning truth is that there is no knowledge of truth, but
finally there is a psychoanalytic knowledge concerning this absence of
knowledge. This is the great paradox of the unconscious...a subject can have an
experience of its proper Real only in the form of an act." (Badiou, 2010)
The analytic transference is nothing but the
allowance of the Real traversal supported by nothing but the formalization of
the matheme: "It is in the very
act of speaking that make this formalization, this ideal meta-language,
ex-sist. It is in this respect that the symbolic cannot be confused with being-
far from it. Rather, it exists qua
ex-sistance with respect to the act of speaking." (SXX, Ibid; pp 119) This
separation is finally that between the pure form of the mathematic inscription, recalcitrant to incorporation within the
symbolic order of language, and the passage to the pure act that deposes all
representational knowledge, and where analytic transference for the traversal
of the phantasy takes place. As Badiou stresses: "This act is like a cut
in language and also a cut in the ordinary representation of the world- a
representation which is imaginary. So the act suddenly isolates the Real from
its normal collection to the imaginary and symbolic orders." (Badiou,
2010).
And
yet we must insist, that for all its purported deflection of knowing-that, the abyss that separates the
voided matheme, suspended from the
Real act and from the symbolic rule of the signifier, merely reproduces the
dyad of signifier/signified in the dichotomy between theoretical inscription
and practical transmission. That is, Lacan reproduces the problem between
thought and reality that he takes to be emblematic of the philosophical forms
of 'knowing' in the tacit distinction between the formal ideography of the matheme in its presentation, and the
singular act of speech in which transference finally takes place. For Lacan
cannot conflate the speciousness of the formulaic writing of the matheme with the act of speech through which the subject traverses the phantasy. That this distinction is ultimately
unexplainable, that the connection between the Real qua formalized matheme
and the Real qua act cannot be articulated, signals the gulf of psychoanalytic
thought, delivered as it is, both to the requirement to forego knowledge, and yet
also to embody it as it tries to give a theory of this process. This
separation ultimately makes the status of the Real undecidable, or fatally
ambiguous, i.e. playing the role of a pure inscription without exteriority (the
Real of the matheme as formalization),
or a pure exteriority without symbolization (the Real is that which resists
symbolization). With the Real subtracted from the traction of knowing, it
becomes a noumenal phantasm suspended between the void of an empty formalism,
or a mystical surrender to the ineffable Otherness that animates the act. Crucially,
the unexplained distinction between the reality of formalization and that of
the act must be supported in the theoretical identification that psychoanalysis
carries vis a vis both the writing matheme and the act of speech, as the
meta-discursive gesture that short-circuits the two in the name of the Real.
And so one notes also, alongside the
obliqueness of the matheme, a desperation against the threat of the
"dialectic" and a helplessness evinced toward the poetic rumination,
thinking from a distance the untouchable purity of an Otherness so unblemished
that it does nothing but subtract itself from the signifier and its operations.
Such is the sliding down to the identification of the Real with that which is
ultimately beyond all capacity for individuation, rendering the conditioning of
the Real of desire excised from its pseudo-objectifications. Unfortunately
then, the question about the legitimacy of desire as a suitable structure to
explain to ontogenesis of thought and being, returns into the market of
theories negotiating an unnamable void for their founding gesture. Perhaps this
is why Lacan struggles, refusing to fully embrace the prospect of ontologizing
the unconscious and desire, to the point of reverting into the desperation of
sophism: "the gap of the unconscious is pre-ontological... it is neither
being nor non-being, but the unrealized." (SXI: pp. 29) It is not only the
structure of unconscious desire that is beyond recalcitrant to ontology: the
object of desire itself is, paradoxically, unobjectifiable insofar as it
remains impossible, non-self identical, never coincident with a being with fixed qualities and properties. This
indicates another level of the fundamental coincide of the non-symbolic
inscription of the object, and the object itself. This is because objet a is both resolutely material (it is localized) and a formal index signaling that which is never
localizable, but which functions as an impasse for meaning, and so which indexes
the asymptotic horizon of the subject's intentional desire. This is why the object
of desire is neither being (it resists objectification or self-identity, thus
enacting the infinity of desire) nor non-being (it must nevertheless be indexed
as impossible object cause, 'if only
to speak of it', as that which consists as inconsistent, subtracting itself
from the signifying chain). The Real object can only be Real insofar as it is
also, and paradoxically, a 'non-object', that is, insofar as it is on the side
of the formal stringency of the matheme
and not of the symbolic-imaginary operations of the signifier. Only the pure
matheme approaches it in its barren formalism by ordaining it to the act of analytic
transference facilitating the traversal of the phantasy.
We must understand thus that the
object cause of desire, qua non-object, is also the mark of the subject qua non-individual; the gap between
itself as conscious (pseudo)-signified being and itself as unconscious signifier
is the gap between the (pseudo) consistency of the individual, and the void of
the subject as well. The void of the subject, tethered to the illusion of the
metonymy of the phallus, is what subtracts itself perpetually from the Oneness
of the individual, in which the subject objectifies itself by having a
signifier stand for it. As Chiesa puts it: "During the process of
subjectivisation three different ontological ‘levels’ of the multiple emerge
retroactively: the inconsistent undead real as not-one; the consistent
multiplicity given by the metonymic slide of the objects of demand (marked as
letters); the subject as split between conscious signified and unconscious
signifier." (Chiesa, 2012, forthcoming).
As a result, the semblance of the
object of the demand in virtue of which 'there is Oneness' constitutes the
intentionality of the subject towards an impossible Real that always eludes its
unifying operation. It is this Real that is designated by the formal opaqueness
of the matheme: "[Objet a] would have us take it for being, in
the name of the following- that it is apparently something. But it only dissolves,
in the final analysis, owing to its failure, unable, as it is, to sustain
itself in approaching the real." (SXX: Pg. 95) The Real of the matheme is therefore non-objective,
since it underlies the symbolic metonymy of signifiers that makes up the phantasy,
which is why the analytic transference that ordains the traversal can't ever be
a matter of knowing or teaching something to the subject,
making it explicit to consciousness, but of intervening
in order to displace the formal localization of the symptom within the unconscious
phantasy. The Real as act is supported thus by the formalization that the matheme, uniquely, subtracts from the
symbolic and the specificity of the demand.
Yet, it must be said, the split
between form and content remains ineludible, and the opaque symbol that
embodies the matheme merely formalizes the possibility of a
transmission of a Real thereby delegated to the act. For Lacan cannot mean that the matheme qua inscription is identical to
the act that transmits in virtue of it, without thereby dissolving the
generality of the theoretical practice with the specificity of the clinical
practice. But in order to separate the two he must be able to explain how the
act itself conforms to the formality of the matheme;
without clarifying what this relation consists in, the claim that
"knowledge becomes act" is itself unintelligible.
We
hear echoes of Heidegger's attempts to reconcile himself with his own theory,
trying to save the Great Outdoors from the clutches of Dasein's world-producing
prerogative (claiming animals have and do not have worlds by saying they are
'poor in them', for instance). Lacan, scavenging for the Real, this being without
the honor of the name, urges the separation between psychoanalysis and
philosophy, much like for Heidegger the poetic thought could only free itself
by separating itself from the loudness of metaphysics. A scission, to be sure, appears
as the uncompromising desire for desire,
stubbornly clinging to its own impossible object, its own unrequited passion.
For the Real does not speak, after all, putting an end to the disguised
epistolary confession of the philosopher and the scientist, as well as the
analysand. Is this not where the tormented psychoanalyst geared towards the
interruption of the symptom by the act and the matheme, and the disillusioned provincialism of the poetic philosopher
traversing metaphysics through poetry meet again: in the desire for silence?
Ultimately, the Real anchor of desire
and its object, this 'indivisible remainder', does not absolve Lacan from the
faith of the philosophical dictum, but rather delivers him back into what Badiou
has called 'the effects of skepticism': "The
effects of this kind of frenzied upsurge, in which the real rules over the
comedy of our symptoms, are ultimately indiscernible from those of skepticism.[15]"
(LOW: Pg. 563) And indeed, I think Badiou is correct here: Lacan's cryptic
statement from 1977 that "truth can only concern the Real" is perhaps
the point of the unique symptom, the torsion where, suspended between the
choice between being and nothingness, Lacan nods for the all-too-familiar
philosophical maneuver, and proceeds to identify them. The sliding void of the
object names the passion for the unnamable stain that, repudiating the
stringency of the symbolic demand, refuses to extirpate itself from thought,
however elusive to its feeble touch. The Real nothingness of Being, and so
philosophy, appears now as the stain for psychoanalysis, refusing to let the
words come to an end. That is, without ever traversing its own fantasy,
absolving the tormented analyst from his own confessional delirium.
Bibliography:
·
Badiou, Alain. Logics of Worlds translated by Alberto
Toscano, Continuum Press, 2006.
·
Badiou, Alain. What is Love?, translated by Sam
Gillespie, Semiotexte, 1999.
·
Badiou Alain, The Scene of the Two, translated by
Barbara P. Fulks, Lacanian Ink, issue 21, 2009.
·
Lacan, Jacques, Seminar XX: Encore, translated by Bruce Fink, Norton Press, 1999.
·
Lacan, Jacques, Seminar XI: The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis,
translated by Bruce Fink, Norton Press, 1998.
·
Lacan, Jacques, Seminar II: The Ego in Freud's Theory and Technique of Psychoanalysis,
Jacques-Alain Miller, Norton, 1991.
·
Lacan, Jacques, Seminar III: The Psychoses, Jacques-Alain Miller, Norton 1998.
·
Lacan, Jacques, Seminar VI: Desire and Its Interpretation, translated by Cormac
Gallagher, , 2009.
·
Lacan, Jacques, Ecrits, translated by Bruce Fink, Norton Press, 2007.
·
Chiesa, Lorenzo, Subjectivity and Otherness: a Philosophical Reading of Lacan, MIT
Press, 2007.
·
Chiesa, Lorenzo, How To Make One Out of a Multiple?, 2012, forthcoming.
·
Žižek, Slavoj, The Parallax View, Verso Books, 2006.
·
Žižek, Slavoj, Tarrying With the Negative, Verso Books, 1993.
·
Žižek, Slavoj, The Sublime Object of Ideology, Verso Books, 1997.
·
Žižek, Slavoj, Woman is One of the Names-of-the-Father, Lacanian Ink 10, 1995.
·
Johnston, Adrian, Žižek's Ontology: A Transcendental Theory of Subjectivity,
Northwestern University Press, 2008.
Index of Abbreviations
E = Ecrits
SII: Seminar II
SIII: Seminar III
SVI: Seminar VI
SXX: Seminar XX
SXI: Seminar XI
Analyst <>
($
<> a)
subject object
Desire
$ <> a
Analyst's Desire
[1] 1. Lacan, Jacques, The
Seminar, Book XX: Encore, On Feminine Sexuality, The Limits of Love and
Knowledge, NY: Norton, 1998, p 48.
[2] Lacan, Jacques, Ecrits:
The First Complete Edition in English, NY: Norton, 1998, p 48
[3]
See for instance Lorenzo Chiesa's (2009) extraordinary systematic
reconstruction.
[4]
Lacan develops how the formative process of the mirror-stage consists of a
‘temporal dialectic’ which t races a line from insufficiency to anticipation,
from need to desire; an ‘orthopaedic’ development. (E: Pg. 692)
[5]
This explains Jacques -Alain Miller's formulation apropos Lacan's teachings
during 1955 under the title "From the small to the big Other", which
also marks Lacan's more pronounced reworking with the structuralist tradition
in linguistics, and thus with the problematic of language in general.
[6] It
is clear that, at least in the 1950's, Lacan's concept of the unconscious is
deeply influence by the Hegelian-Kojevian notion of desire as the desire of
recognition of the other.
[7] I present the graph of desire in its second
form, since it should suffice at that stage for our present purposes For these
graphs see (SVI, L1, pp. 7, 12; E, pp. 681-688)
[8]
Slavoj Zizek has famously proposed to read this operation of retroactive
determination along the lines of Kripke’s account of rigid designation; where
the point of caption where the
subject pierces the big Other fixes a referent for the signifying statement
like a rigid designator. For the details see Zizek, The Sublime Object of Ideology, Chapter III, Pg 206.
[9]
Indeed, the word "ontology" is not mentioned once in Seminar VI.
[10]
See Appendix I for an illustration
[11]
Roughly, from Seminar XI onwards.
[12]
Even if we agree with Badiou that psychoanalysis is indeed closer to politics
in seeking the singularity of the individual symptom rather than the repetition
of the scientific thought, it must be stressed that, irrespective of the
clinical practice, the theoretical endeavor carried out by psychoanalytic
thought cannot but be subject to the norms of conceptual consistency which
binds scientific thought. If this is the case, then the way that psychoanalysis
shields itself against the dogmatism of embracing alienation in the signifier
to its fullest extent would not be to simply listen to the 'affirmative'
vocation of political thought, but also to the scientific vocation for what
renders its theoretical posits possible, i.e. formal coherency of its
ideography.
[13] Lacan, J., Le triomphe de la religion, précedé
du Discours aux catholiques, Paris: Seuil 2005, p. 96, 97.
[14]
This is why Zizek calls "the scientific Real" that "...of a formula which renders the
nature's meaningless functioning." (Zizek, How to Read Lacan, http://www.lacan.com/zizalien.htm)
[15]
In this regard, I would emphasize that, in spite of Badiou's commendable
attempts to characterize psychoanalysis as a candidate for thinking but perhaps not a science,
where the latter term is understood as "the unity of a theory and a
practice", does not help solve the issue. This can be easily seen if we
realize that the incapacity to separate theory and practice is not something we
can straightforwardly allot to science; even if psychoanalysis is thought as
closer to politics, the question about the relation between the statements of such a thought and the
thing itself remains. To stipulate an absolute inseparability between thought
and world is to surrender to idealism; to claim such a distinction is possible
is to rehabilitate the valence of knowing within a philosophical thought. I
believe, for reasons that Ray Brassier has pointed out, following Wilfrid
Sellars, that the methodological
separation between the space of reasons and the space of causes is the
condition of possibility for the ontological
unity between thought and being, reason and nature. The consequence, against
Badiou's depiction, is not a thinking of the articulation between a theory and
a praxis, but rather how such an
articulation is to be understood as that between world that is not thought and
thought that thinks the world.
16 comentarios:
I almost never comment, but i did some searching
and wound up here "The Desire for Desire: Can Psychoanalysis Speak About?".
And I actually do have a few questions for you if you tend not to mind.
Could it be only me or does it look like a few of these responses appear
as if they are written by brain dead individuals? :-P And, if you are posting at additional places, I'd like to keep up with anything new you have to post. Would you make a list of the complete urls of all your community pages like your Facebook page, twitter feed, or linkedin profile?
Feel free to surf to my blog :: Seafood
You made some really good points there. I checked on the
net for additional information about the issue and found most individuals will go along with your views on this website.
Also visit my web site :: personal injury attorney
What's up i am kavin, its my first time to commenting anywhere, when i read this piece of writing i thought i could also create comment due to this good article.
My webpage: St Cloud Floral
I don't leave a bunch of remarks, but i did a few searching and wound up here "The Desire for Desire: Can Psychoanalysis Speak About?". And I actually do have some questions for you if it's allright.
Could it be simply me or does it look like some of the comments look like they are coming from brain dead individuals?
:-P And, if you are posting on additional online sites, I would like to follow everything new you have to post.
Would you make a list of every one of all your communal pages like your twitter feed,
Facebook page or linkedin profile?
Feel free to visit my blog post - Florist
Wow, that's what I was exploring for, what a information! existing here at this web site, thanks admin of this site.
Feel free to visit my blog - short game instruction
Your means of explaining everything in this article is genuinely good,
every one can simply be aware of it, Thanks a lot.
Feel free to visit my blog post - golf cart covers yamaha
It is the best time to make some plans for the future and it
is time to be happy. I have read this post and if I
could I want to suggest you some interesting things or advice.
Perhaps you can write next articles referring
to this article. I desire to read more things about it!
Here is my site - top golf schools north carolina
Hello! This is the second time visiting now and I
just wanted to say I truley relish looking at your blog site.
I decided to bookmark it at stumbleupon.com with your title:
Blogger: Being's Poem and your Web address: http://www.blogger.com/comment.g?blogID=6580039155018603814&postID=5224489696551426649. I hope this is ok with you, I'm trying to give your good blog a bit more publicity.
Be back soon.
Have a look at my web page :: auto insurance in missouri
Howdy! Do you know if they make any plugins to protect against hackers?
I'm kinda paranoid about losing everything I've worked hard on.
Any recommendations?
Feel free to visit my web site dedham auto insurance
Hi there, i read your blog from time to time and i
own a similar one and i was just wondering if you get a lot of spam remarks?
If so how do you protect against it, any plugin or anything you can advise?
I get so much lately it's driving me insane so any support is very much appreciated.
my homepage :: aapa physician assistant
Hi would you mind letting me know which webhost you're working with? I've loaded your blog in 3 completely different
web browsers and I must say this blog loads a lot quicker then most.
Can you recommend a good web hosting provider
at a honest price? Cheers, I appreciate it!
My page home equity credit line loan
Just desire to say your article is as amazing. The
clarity to your put up is simply cool and that i can assume you are
knowledgeable in this subject. Well together with your permission allow me to grab your
RSS feed to stay up to date with imminent post. Thanks one million and please continue
the gratifying work.
Also visit my web site ... athletic injuries to the head neck and face
First of all I want to say great blog! I had a quick question
that I'd like to ask if you do not mind. I was interested to find out how you center yourself and clear your head before writing. I have had a tough time clearing my mind in getting my ideas out there. I truly do enjoy writing however it just seems like the first 10 to 15 minutes tend to be lost just trying to figure out how to begin. Any recommendations or hints? Appreciate it!
my site; cheap kitchen appliances packages
I am actually glad to read this website posts
which includes plenty of valuable information, thanks for providing these information.
My site; golf gloves
Great article! This is the type of information that are supposed to be shared around the internet.
Shame on the seek engines for no longer positioning this submit higher!
Come on over and discuss with my web site . Thank you =)
Also visit my site :: http://golf-mi.com/
Great article, totally what I wanted to find.
Check out my blog post ... certified athletic trainer information
Publicar un comentario