viernes, 31 de agosto de 2012

Can Psychoanalysis Speak About? The Cunning of Knowing


- CAN PSYCHOANALYSIS SPEAK ABOUT? -
The Cunning of Knowing
___________________________________

Abstract/Introduction

        Throughout the majority of his work, Lacan purported to establish psychoanalysis not just as an autonomous discipline with respect to empirical psychology and the philosophy of mind, but as a clinical and theoretical practice that would reveal what underlies the very pretensions of those disciplines. A theory of desire, advancing towards the point of scientific formalization, promised to simultaneously explain and underdetermine conceptions of subjectivity, consciousness, knowledge, and being that preoccupied both philosophers and psychologists for centuries. The question about whether psychoanalysis is a science therefore can be said to supervene on whether it can position itself as a theory of the libidinal undergirding of philosophy and psychology. Whether psychoanalysis can indeed fulfill the promise it set itself with Lacan remains as much of an open question as if the one about its scientific status. This essay examines how psychoanalysis attempts to constitute itself as a theory.

           In what follows, I set myself two aims. First, following Alain Badiou, I seek to clarify the way in which Lacanian psychoanalysis appropriates and challenges philosophy, following the characterization of Lacan as an 'anti-philosopher'. Second, I suggest that an answer to this question reveals a fundamental quandary in the psychoanalytic edifice, ultimately rendering dubious both the status of psychoanalysis as a theory and as a clinical practice. More specifically, I argue that this predicament results from the attempt to elide the referential relation between mind and world, signifier and signified, that characterizes representational thought, in favor of the structuralist relation between signifiers that theorizes desire's inscription into the symbolic order, wherein philosophical propositions are negotiated as well. This alternative account is then coupled to a subtractive notion of the Real that refuses incorporation into the linguistic order. In short, Lacan’s subject of desire attempts to deflate the ontological-epistemological valences from his theory by supplanting the structuralist articulation between signifiers for the representationalist relation of reference between words and things.

 It is this re-articulation between the Real and the conceptual-linguistic order of the signifier that I seek to evince as problematic, in its purported demotion of representation and the philosophical task proper. I therefore propose to read Lacan's account of the unconscious as a bold, but nevertheless failed attempt to supersede empirical conceptions of the subject, epistemological accounts of knowledge and desire, and ontological conceptions of objective being. I claim that as a result psychoanalysis fails not only to secure its scientific status, but more generally its theoretical status as well.

 (a) The Oedipus Complex and the Imaginary - A Mythical Prelude  
         But in order to make our contention clear, a few preliminaries are well in order. First, we must understand precisely in what way Lacan's account of the symbolic and the Real purports to hijack traditional philosophical attempts to describe consciousness and knowledge, subjectivity and objectivity. This proximity to philosophical (and not just psychological) problems, remains a remarkable feature that sets Lacan apart from Freud's germinal psychoanalytic endeavor. For as Alain Badiou (2010) brings to attention, it is only in Lacan's work that we see psychoanalysis routinely reference, address and challenge the great Western philosophical tradition[1].

          And yet, Badiou also reminds us, this relation is not one of continuation or of the integration of psychoanalysis into the philosophical itinerary. Rather, Lacan deploys the term 'anti-philosophy' to characterize his position vis a vis philosophy, and wages against the latter, as every anti-philosopher attempts, hijacking from within the framework of questions and concepts that philosophy negotiates. In its Lacanian guise, the usurping of philosophical concepts is carried forth in the name of a theory of desire, which includes the philosophical desire for knowledge and truth, both about the subject and the world. Badiou writes that, "It is typical of anti-philosophy that its purpose is never to discuss any philosophical theses... since to do so it would have to share its norms (for instance, those of the true and the false). What the anti-philosopher wants to do is to situate the philosophical desire in its entirety in the register of the erroneous and the harmful." (WAP; Pg. 77; emphasis added). Only once we have understood the grounds for the psychoanalytic attempt to simultaneously reveal and challenge the feasibility and propriety of the philosophical desire as a desire will we be in a position to assess psychoanalysis' own "position of enunciation" with respect to philosophy. In order to do this, I propose first to briefly exegetically examine how Lacan carries forth his re-elaboration of the classical philosophical concepts outlined above, so as to articulate them anew in a theory of desire that would suffice to characterize not only philosophy, but yield a structural understanding of how discourse emerges and is entangled with desire in different ways, and according to general structural principles.

       In this regard, the point of departure is, nevertheless, already the Freudian one: to supplement an understanding of conscious psychic life, by way of an account of the unconscious dimension that animates subjective life. Crossbreeding the structuralist avowal of the primacy of the signifier with the Freudian account of the unconscious, Lacan proposes thus to articulate a theory of subjective desire around the singular idea that “the unconscious is structured like a language”[2]. This enigmatic formula is to be understood by way of Lacan's re-construction of the Freudian Oedipal myth, which leads to thinking of the subject as constitutively affected by loss, that is, seeing its being as lacking in relation to an ideal image. Lacan writes: "The domain of the Freudian experience is established within a very different register of relations. Desire is a relation of being to lack. This lack is the lack of being properly speaking. It isn’t the lack of this or that, but lack of being whereby the being exists. This lack is beyond anything which can represent it. It is only ever represented as a reflection on a veil. The libido, but now no longer as used theoretically as a quantitative quantity, is the name of what animates the deep-seated conflict at the heart of human action…."[3] The "lack of being" or the idea of being-as-lack condenses the  idea that the Real of the subject is never commensurate to the ideal identities that representation yields for conscious thought. Yet, as we shall see, this eventually leads Lacan to fully separate the ontological domain of being proper to philosophy and ontology, still engrossed in the symbolic commerce of the signifier, from the domain of the Real desire, which subtracts itself from the symbolic and which it falls to psychoanalysis to examine. Philosophy, according to Lacan, masks the vacuity of a Real subjectivity in the name of knowing, through the objective seal of the signifier and the idealities it projects.


But how does the Real of this voided subject, incommensurate to any substantive identity, relate to the signifying order, if not by way of gaining traction before being in representation? And similarly, how does the subject come to misapprehend or think itself in the guise of the signifier, as having a fixed identity? Finally, what kind of operation or place of enunciation does psychoanalytic discourse carry out in order to be able to speak about this formal subjectivity and the libidinal structure in which language becomes nested in; wherefrom does psychoanalysis issue its address? How does one produce a theory about the articulation between the symbolic commerce of the signifier along its imaginary-ideal envelopments, and the Real, without claiming we do so by representing the latter, as philosophers and psychologists purport to do? It is towards answering these questions that we are headed in what follows.


            The Lacanian answer to the first two questions come of a piece. First, for Lacan, the subject finds and identifies itself outside of itself, in the form of an object for thought or an ideal correlate, that it intends towards and seeks to become equal to. It is this ideal unity which simultaneously forms the basis of what the subject identifies itself as, but also of what positions it in the course of an impossible desire for 'reconstitution'. This decentered (mis)identification of the subject with an-other, indicates that the ideal identity of one's individuated identity emerges from a structural alienation of the subject from itself, a lack that makes subjectivity not fully coincide with the ideality thus projected. It is insofar as the subject is never equal to its projected identity that desire, as an infinite tendency, hovers asymptotically around an impossible object-cause (which Lacan famously calls objet petit a): " …. Desire, a function central to all human experience, is the desire for nothing nameable. And at the same time this desire lies at the origin of every variety of animation. If being were only what it is, there wouldn’t even be room to talk about it. Being comes into existence as an exact function of this lack. Being attains a sense of self in relation to being as a function of this lack, in the experience of desire."[4] The ideality of whatever the subject imagines and explicitly relates to is then nothing but the symptom or point in its psyche, wherein  the empty reality of the impossible object-cause fixes itself.

         But what is the relation between this underlying object-cause, or the impossible Real object of desire on the one hand, and the also impossible ideal-investments which make up the objective figurations of the subject, and which constitute its illusory identity as an individual? Lacan's will answer by explaining the intentionality of consciousness and explicit "knowing" towards illusory ideals in terms of the intentionality of unconscious desire, as oriented towards the impossible Real object. We could tentatively propose that Lacan's initial coup against philosophy and psychology consists in positing that the libidinal intentionality of the unconscious founds the cognitive intentionality of consciousness by way of alienation. But in order to distinguish the Real dimension object from the imagined semblances that the phantasy of the subject projects, Lacan is forced into both identifying former with its formal dimension (as opposed to 'substantive' or ontological dimension), and subtract it from the commerce of the signifier wherein discourse tethers itself symptomatically. We shall first focus on the latter question, which provides the answer to how psychoanalysis attempts to trump philosophy, only then to move towards setting up a controversy as made evident by considering the second question.
         
    Psychoanalysis must hold this prerogative as the study of desire, since it is desire that evinces itself as the motor for any kind of intentional comportment towards being or entities. Lacan's account seeks to reveal how the objectivation of intentional consciousness is underdetermined by the psychic split that follows from the Oedipal castration-complex, and in which the subject is wrested from the immanent symbiosis with maternal body and into the order of the transcendental Law or language, thereby intending towards the recovery of the non-alienation which is thought to be lost. Insofar as every knowledge intends towards an object, all epistemological or phenomenological investigation into consciousness and its contents are uniformly treated as iterations implicating the same structure of psychic splitting or alienation. And it is on the basis of this shared libidinal structure that Lacan seeks to frame psychoanalysis as a theory that accesses the libidinal kernel behind philosophy and psychology.

        The core of the account involves tracing how the specular images that the subject builds an identity from support desire by being correlated to "the signifying chain" the symbolic or language, i.e. how the subject enters the "defiles through the signifier" within which the subject will circulate around the (impossible) object of desire: "There are in the unconscious signifying chains which subsist as such, and which from there structure, act on the organism, influence what appears from the outside as a symptom, and this is the whole basis of analytic experience.[5]"  Following Zizek, we can call the splitting of the subject symbolic castration, to describe how the division and articulation between the subject and its imaginary identifications is relative to how the subject becomes enjoined and invested from an impersonal cultural-linguistic order. Or, to quote Zizek, symbolic castration obtains where the "...gap between what I really am' and the symbolic mask that makes the subject into something. The subject is thus castrated from the 'real' "I" by projecting something else."[6] (Zizek, HRL, Pg. 34)

        The basic idea is that who the subject thinks it is or should be, its placing, so to speak, is determined on the basis of a language that he acquires by external conditioning, and never immediately or transparently as phenomenologists surmise. For Lacan, the self-alienation of the subject founds the notion of an ontologically consistent individual, identical to itself, thereby veiling the (unbridgeable) gap between its immediate (non)-being (or the void of its formal subjectivity) and its imaginary-symbolic figurations (which yield 'empirical' content).  Because self-relation and self-constitution is paradoxically grounded in this moment of self-alienation, it is both the moment of narcissism and that of absolute estrangement: "One can sense, one can pick up that narcissism is involved somewhere, and that this narcissism is involved at this moment of the Oedipus complex." (S6, L6, pp. 92)

        The "great outdoors" coveted by the philosophers turns out on this account to be a function of a subject that by virtue of desiring is split between the object it identifies itself with, and the formal void which subtracts itself from every such identification. Lacan's contentions against philosophy and psychology converge here, radicalizing the Kantian separation between the transcendental and empirical subject, that Zizek characterizes as a decisive mark of the modern breakthrough[7]. Lacan's appropriation of this split, however, defuses any attempts to reify the transcendence of the subject in terms of a consciousness furnished with a priori cognitive structures to individuate its contents[8].

          This entails that the unity and emergence of what Freud called the "perception-consciousness system" that characterizes thinking beings is to be explained by placing it in contrast to a notion of subjectivity that is recalcitrant with that of the ego qua decentered other. Consciousness is of the order of the ego, since it thinks that it is the imaginary projection of itself outside of itself that does the thinking, i.e. it identifies itself with what it thinks. But Lacan's point is precisely that the desiring subject is never such identical to what in intends towards as its objective pole, but precisely the contrary, and against Descartes, it thinks where it is not. This marks accordingly the foreclosure of all attempts to think of the subject of the unconscious as topic for "empirical" investigation. Desire entails, in short, a Gestalt, conditioning the entire field of the visible world; the individuated world of things and persons actually presupposes the structure of the subject of desire. As a result, the imaginary that furnishes the disclosure or revelation of being to man, the ideal investments, so dear to the philosopher, are suddenly made to appear as the ploy of desire's interminable ruse for the subject's self-reconstitution.

            Alienation therefore effectuates a commensuration between the images projected from the perspective of the subject's alienation, and the 'visible world' of things. It serves simultaneously as the germinal point of entry for both the epistemological myth of a fully consistent subject or self, as well as for the ontological myth of a fully consistent object or other; that is, for both philosophy and empirical (ego) psychology.  In other words, the subject-object dichotomy, from which both philosophy and psychology depart, begins in the infant's (mis)identification and de-centering: the idea that one's being lacks any unified substantiality or 'selfhood' (the pure membra disjecta) emerges as a result of the identification with a subsistent image.  It is my primary identification with an image that locates a gap between the reality of the subject as the agent of thought and as an object of thought. This seems to be the meaning behind the cryptic statement from Lacan that the ego, in its narcissistic stupor, constitutes "...a vital dehiscence that is constitutive of man" (E, pp. 4) But if the philosophical quest for knowledge and consciousness are unknowingly submitted to the rule of desire, then it what sense does psychoanalysis escape this fate? How does psychoanalysis prevent itself from trying to know in accordance to its own figurations, to the own reified individuality of the analyst, to occupy the position of being an observer of discourse? Indeed, is there room to speak of knowledge of desire, once we have demoted the idea that consciousness apprehends in representational terms? It is at this juncture that Lacan must reconstruct the traditional philosophical relation of representational congruence between words and things for the structuralist flattening relations that hold between signifiers in 'chains'.

          Thus, the next step, for us, is to explain how the imaginary functions of the ideal ego are at the same time mediated by the cultural order of language, the "(big) Other", which signals that it constitutes a decentered place of identification, like the other of the imaginary, but also an impersonal field constituted by the community into which one is inserted[9]. By tethering the subject of the unconscious to the symbolic Lacan means to say that language is in a sense a transcendent authority that ordains and issues the injunctions before which desire sets itself. Desire is the desire of the Other precisely insofar as it is mediated by an order or Law which pre-exists and determines its organization[10]. Or, put differently, one never desires what one sees or imagines immediately, but only through particular prescriptions and normative injunctions issued from the impersonal order of language. Chiesa explains that "...the specular, alienating identification of the subject with the imaginary other necessarily presupposes an earlier, original - and perpetual- alienation in the Other qua language." (Chiesa, 2009, pp. 25)

         In order to understand the (anti)-philosophical significance of this move, consider the following classical statement from Pufendorf, issued at the beginning of the Enlightenment, on the institution of norms by the rational adherence of individual agents: "[W]hen a man of his own accord consents to the rule of another, he acknowledges by his own act that he must follow what he himself has decided."[11] The same idea is later found in Kant, for whom it is the rational capacity for individuals to bind themselves to linguistically articulated norms that simultaneously subject them to authority and assessment, but also are the condition for their freedom and choice. Rationality endows the subject the capacity for freedom insofar as it reckons its power for adhering to the prescriptions issued as linguistic norms or laws. Ye who is it that binds itself freely, in advance of all prescriptions?

           Lacan's point is that in order to 'freely' bind oneself to a norm one must, already be bound by the Other, and that therefore, strictly speaking, there is no 'free' binding. For an individual to recognize itself as bound to a norm he/she must be already in possession of an inherited language  in terms of which he/she formulates his/her identity. This individual who presumably binds itself freely is then, to use an Althusserian expression, always already interpellated by the big Other, rather than the condition for the institution of the big Other. One always chooses that which has already been chosen; it is always from within language that one formulates the fantasy of a 'free' binding, or of the individuality required thereof. It is not a conscious self-recognition which allows one to bind oneself to linguistic norms; one must be already implicitly and unconsciously bound to norms in order to desire and think of a possible self-recognition. This individual who 'recognizes itself as free to bind itself' is thereby supplanted, by Lacan, for a subject who cannot but fail to recognize itself in the identity that is prescribed to him from the big Other. There is no meta-language, no position of an observer: "The subject is nothing other than what slides in a chain of signifiers, whether he knows which signifier he is the effect of or not. That effect- the subject – is the intermediary effect between what characterizes a signifier and another signifier, namely, the fact that each of them, each of them is an element. "[12]

       This leads us to question, then, about what possible role could psychoanalysis occupy within the 'sliding chain of signification', as it mediates the clinical intervention of the analyst by way of a corpus of theoretical claims that describe and prescribe the very subject matter for psychoanalysis? Indeed, what is the ethics of this peculiar discursive enterprise that warns against the temptation to position oneself as an external observer before the parade of signifiers? Who is, after all, the subject of psychoanalysis, and from what position does it issue its address? This question becomes pressing the more we realize that the very clinical practice psychoanalysis enacts is itself mediated by the series of principles, statements and formulas that comprise the 'theory' of psychoanalysis, and without which its practice in the clinical setting would be impossible. How does the 'binding' to these principles take place' in accordance to what rule, if not that prescribed by the big Other?  In order to see how this problem becomes particularly acute we must see how the Lacanian conception of a voided subjectivity in tandem with his adherence to a immanent structuralism within the order of the signifier leads to the problematic assessment of psychoanalytic claims, and finally to a quandary concerning its position of address. This becomes evident once we realize Lacan's liquidation of representation is the very condition for his claim that there is no meta-language. Let us examine the details involved in Lacan's account.

         As we have seen, the logical priority of the symbolic entails both that the self-identification of the subject with the imago occurs as the subject is inserted into language, and that the identification of others as others (both individuals and objects, persons and things) is conditioned by the linguistic order of the signifier, i.e. individuation is a function of language, and this articulates both the epistemic-psychological dimensions of self-understanding, as well as the ontological dimensions of understanding others and the world[13].  This forms a necessary corrective the myths of knowledge and thinking that located desire at the level of explicit consciousness, since for them "... it seemed that consciousness was inherent to what the subject had to say qua signification" (SV, pp. 105).

          Redoubling the earlier distinction between individual ego and subject, at the level of the symbolic we can map the distinction between the subject of the statement and the subject of enunciation. The former is expressly formulated in speech or writing, individuated by the inclusion into the symbolic order and grammatically objectivated within the sequences of signifiers and sentences that structure discourse. The subject of the enunciation, on the other hand,  is the slippery index for the subject of the unconscious, which remains forever subtracted and incomplete from desire’s imaginary-symbolic operations, and from the statement. Lacan reverses Descartes dictum accordingly: "I think where I am not, therefore I am where I do not think" (Lacan 1977: 166).

         However, the most important point we must underline here is that the subject of enunciation does not stand to the subject of the statement as signified stands to signifier, or represented to representing. Lacan is adamant to insist in that the individuating function of the big Other is not merely representationalist in the sense that it 'tracks down things' through words or signs; it refuses to be ontologised or positivized. This constitutes the kernel of Lacan's flattening of the Saussurian relation of signification as holding between signs and things, to one where signification obtains between signifiers exclusively: "The signifier doesn't just provide an envelope, a receptacle for signification. It polarizes it, it structures it, and brings it into existence." (SIII, pp. 224), and "...the sign does not take its value with respect to a third thing that it represents, but it takes on its value with respect to another signifier which it is not." (Ibid; pp. 7) Or yet again: "The signifier is a sign that doesn't refer to any object... It is a sign which refers to another sign, which is as such structured to signify the absence of another sign, in other words, to be opposed to it in a couple." (SXI, pp. 167)

         What I would like to suggest is that it is not only the subject of the unconscious which becomes delivered from the empirical pretences of ego-psychology or transcendental philosophy into the order of language, but also the intended objects of consciousness which become delivered from the empirical pretences of metaphysicians and ontologists to the delirium of the signifier. As a result, the unconscious is crucially neither the subject, nor an object; it has no determinate ontological or epistemic status: "...what still becomes apparent to anyone in analysis who spends some time observing what truly belongs to the order of the unconscious, is that it is neither being, nor non-being, but the unrealized." (SXI, pp 30)


    As a result, the disjunction between psychoanalysis and philosophy is total since "the gap of the unconscious seems to be pre-ontological... it does not lend itself to ontology" (Ibid. 29) The psychoanalytic relation to the non-ontologizable  reality of the unconscious is not the search for a pre-linguistic positive content hidden behind the signifying chain, which would constitute the ‘real subject’ after sublating and shedding off its feeble illusions[14]. Whereas the subject of knowledge is an illusion, the subject of the unconscious is not merely a myth: "the subject [of knowledge] correlative to the object, the subject around whom turns the eternal question of idealism, and who is himself an ideal subject...he is only supposed." (S6, L2, pp. 18). It is not the ideal subject that underlies the signifier, but the pure formal placement of signifiers that comprises the subject: " The subject is nothing other than what slides in a chain of signifiers, whether he knows which signifier he is the effect of or not".[15] As a result, both subject and object are delivered to a structure of signification, void of any ontological status, and to relations between signifiers, void of epistemological status.

              And yet, does this leave it open that something like being-as-such may nonetheless subsist in the order of consciousness, along its much vaunted intentionality? For if indeed, as Lacan puts it, "the Freudian world isn't a world of things, it isn't a world of being, it is a world of desire as such", then couldn't the relation of knowing in which things, and not just words, come into mind, be said to subsist at some level? (S2, pp. 222) Yet insofar as the relation between words and things is flattened to the relation between signifiers, ontology could only be said to subsist trivially at the price of subordinating it to the structure of desire. This weakens the ontological valence of 'beings' or 'being' to merely ideal poles for the phantasies of philosophers, which does not so much deny ontology as much as it suspends its purported prerogative when securing our access to the "world of being", understood as that of a mind independent reality. It thereby flattens the philosophical pretence of gaining traction before the world to the uniform register of an unconscious desire which, like every other, is supported in nothing else than in the signifying chain and its metonymic inscriptions. As Alain Badiou puts it: "An important consequence of this situation is, in this instance, the fact that the void is not  presupposed in signification from the perspective of its universality.  It is presupposed under signification,  at the back of signification, as the slipping, the sliding, the streaming and the channel of  our being, in the unpresented that doubles the signifying chain" (Badiou, Umbra, Pg. 28)

              This answer seems to preemptively defang ontology from its capacity to prey on the world, after which its peculiarity becomes a matter of organization at the level of signifier. In this regard, Badiou's reading of Lacan as an anti-philosopher stresses how, once demoted to one more discursive practice among others, psychoanalysis would carry out "a deposing of the category of philosophy to constitute itself as theory... philosophy is an act, of which the fabulations about 'truth' are the clothing, the propaganda, the lies." (Badiou, 2010, pp 75) I will later suggest why it is not clear, however, that psychoanalysis can legitimize itself as a theory without reactivating the kinds of distinctions it takes to be proper of philosophico-scientific discourse, and will proceed to ask what consequences follow for the formal coherence of psychoanalysis, as well as for its purported content. That is to say, we shall ask how psychoanalysis relates to its subject matter.

        Since there is no substantive content proper to the voided, barred subject and no statement which predicates its 'proper being', Lacan consistently claims that there is no Other of the Other: that there is no subject to be captured ‘outside’ of the Otherness of language or, what amounts to the same, that “…there is no metalanguage.” (E, 688) Put differently, one never "reaches out" outside of language, either directly onto an other subject, or, what amounts to the same, to being as an object, since "...what characterizes the demand is not just that it is a relationship of a subject to another subject [or between a subject and an object], it is that this relationship is made through the mediation of language, through the mediation of a system of signifiers." (SVI, L3, pp. 27) The movement of the Real occurs by and through the order of the signifier, not as a foreign transcendence. The primitive individuation of the imaginary realm, which as we saw constitutes the entire field of the visible, traverses the order of the signifier constituting the vain phantasy to regain the impossible object which would endow its void with an integral consistency.

  (c) The Cunning of Being or the Being of Cunning?
     If the subject of the reality unconscious is indeed structured like a language, and desire is nothing but that which slides in the articulation between signifiers, then the much vaunted Freudian 'world of desire' is an idealized world populated by phantasms; not a world as much as the height of narcissistic alienation, the nightmare which is nothing but a dream come true. At this point we should ask again: does this mean that even if the relation of knowing between words and things does not hold good for the structure of the unconscious, it might nevertheless be thinkable within the realm of consciousness?

           In this stronger formulation, I believe that the question must be answered to in the negative. For it is clear that the "Freudian world" isn't just another world which, in dualist metaphysical spirits, would neatly leave the innocence of the world of knowing to its own operations, untouched. Indeed, Lacan is adamant to show not only that the world of desire is not the world of things, but that the unconscious conditions the operations of consciousness and seals its every pretence within the economy of desire: "Relations between human beings are really established before one gets to the domain of consciousness. It is desire which achieves the primitive structuration of the human world, desire as unconscious." (S2, pp. 224) More dramatically still, it's precisely desire's undermining of consciousness that makes the explicit conscious claims to the universality of being subordinate to the unconscious singularity of the symptom, or as Lacan reminds us: "...don't forget that consciousness isn't universal." (Ibid). If this is so, then the ontological independence of the 'realm of things' could at best be an epiphenomenal illusion, a veil under which the iterations of desire and the symptom displace themselves in the order of the signifier.


 In fact, Lacan explicitly subordinates the object of knowledge to the object of desire, and claims that in the vector leading from the barred subject to its decentered other, the small impossible object of desire, one finds the (illusion) of knowledge: "$ [stands] in the presence of o and which we call the phantasy, which  in the psychic economy represents something that you know." (Ibid, pp 214). This is why it is, paradoxically, desire that is the metonymy of being in the subject, insofar as it is through the self-alienating insertion into the impersonal Other of language that the subject releases its intentionality, and not from the realm of "Being" that offers itself 'as a gift' to immediate experience. What philosophers reify as knowledge of being is in truth the knowledge of the Other, insofar as it is attributed to and assumed by the subject as individuated in the impersonal symbolic order: ""What is it that knows?" Do we realize that it is the Other?... as a locus in which the signifier is posited, as without which nothing indicates to us that there is a dimension of truth anywhere, a di-mension, the residence of what is said, of this said whose knowledge posits the Other as locus." (SXX, pp. 96)

          The philosophical questioning that aims at knowledge is thus to be understood as the subject's depositing of his speech within the punctuation of the symbolic, rather than by corresponding to the Real. The power of the question brings us closer not to a palpitating realm behind the order of the signifier, but  only to the demand issued from within this order; thought must subordinate its positivity to it, and find itself always-already lost in it. For the subject, "what he is questioning himself about is far from being the response, it is the questioning. It is effectively 'What is this signifier of the Other in me?" (S1, L9, pp. 132). By fixating itself into the order of the signifier, ruminating in search for the impossible lost object, the quest for self proves, ironically, an inversion of the philosophical genealogy of thought, a predecessor of the quest for being as such: "... the bar is the hidden signifier, the one that the Other does not have at its disposition, and which is precisely the one which concerns you: it is the same one that makes you enter the game in so far as you, poor simpletons, since you were born, were caught up in this sacred logos business." (Ibid; L16, pp. 207). And indeed it is telling that the quest for being should be of no concern for the psychoanalyst, but that he rather makes of desire that which deserves to be called "the essence of man", signaling its logical, if not chronological, priority (S6, L1, pp 4)[16].

      However, this predicament forces psychoanalysis into a quandary. For if the subject of knowledge is indeed subordinate to the unconscious, and if the relation between signifier and signified is flattened to the chains in the former, how are we to understand what for Lacan, indeed for psychoanalysis, must be a theory of desire? That is, how can Lacanian psychoanalysis, in erecting its formidable conceptual structure, proclaim to give a structured theory and not just constitute an improvised practice, i.e. how is it to become a discourse in which the structural features of desire are outlined and articulated? For if there is no relation between words and things, then what relation do the theoretical statements formulated in psychoanalysis purportedly bear to its presumed subject matter? What is the role of the peculiar signifier "desire" in the economy of psychoanalysis, if there is, strictly speaking, nothing 'out there' to be spoken of, no 'thing' populating the world which can escape the latency of the phantasy?  And similarly for 'unconscious', 'signifier', "subject", the entire roster of concepts that psychoanalysis deploys continuously, when claiming to explain the generality of desire as a structure, and not just as manifesting one more iteration of desire as a symptom, like every other.

          Preemptively, one might answer that indeed because psychoanalysis elides the priority of the referential relation it is never trying to 'reach out' onto things or to give an ontology, peeking behind the words, but is rather consigned to survey the latent content in which the signifying chains become deployed and used. Thereby, the analyst is not a knower, claiming to access the 'things behind the appearances', since that would performatively contradict the purported demotion of epistemology/psychology and philosophy by reifying the subject supposed to know into a kernel for empirical investigation. Rather, the analyst is concerned with the reality of appearances only, with how they find their place within the structure of signification as such.

         But this is simply to inflect the issue into the order of language. For if psychoanalysis is not just one more phantasy caught around its impossible object, then this is because what Lacan is effectively doing is not simply writing/speaking to us qua analysands, addressing the particularity of our (paradoxically) universal symptom. Rather, he is outlining the general structure of desire. In other words, the statements issued by psychoanalysis allegedly pertain not just to one more discourse in the same footing before desire as all others, but must rather gain traction before desire as such. If not, then the artifice of psychoanalytic claims and formalizations would do nothing but make of the signifier "desire" its very own symbolic fiction, another specular symptom fixing the localization of an impossible object, in an attempt to wage against the organization of the purported hegemony of philosophers and psychologists. Yet Lacan repeatedly insists on both the preponderance of a Real that is radically recalcitrant to any symbolization on the one hand, and which is also the subject of psychoanalsysis itself. How are we to understand the relation between the claims of psychoanalysis and the Real that it comports itself towards? From where can psychoanalysis issue an address about the Real without reifying an epistemological relation between knower and known, which would depend on an ontologized conception of subjectivity?

           First, it is clear that the position of enunciation that corresponds to the analyst's theoretical statements and formalizations cannot be rendered equivalent to the position he/she occupies as an analyst in the clinical setting[17]. But wherein is this theoretical meta-discourse to be located then? How does it escape the impersonal pretences of the University discourse, or the hegemonic address of the Master discourse? How does it function in abstraction from the commerce of the symbol?

        These questions are pressing, since the theoretical claims of psychoanalysis function as the transcendental condition for the division between the different formalizations of discursive positions, and so also for the delineation of the analyst's role apropos the other three positional registers. It seems to be, in this sense, functioning as a kind of exception to the discursive hegemony of signifiers circling around the object-cause with respect to the place of the signifier. But this is precisely the kind of meta-linguistic position that Lacan seemingly wants to avoid at all costs, and it is not clear on which methodological grounds one could purport to occupy such an exceptional position while denying the valence of transcendence which conditions epistemological investigation. The transcendental regulation by the theoretical, however, seems function as the condition for the displacement of philosophy, by assuming the epistemic rights before desire as a structure, and against being and ontology. Thus, the theorerical claims of psychoanalysis condition both the typology of subjective positions fro outside, as well as the variegated semantic valences that give meaning to its own claims about the Real.

         I would suggest that, if as Badiou insists, Lacan is an anti-philosopher, it is insofar as in waging war against the ontological phantasy, he nevertheless remains within its confines; where the position of enunciation of the University and the claim to objective knowledge, that is, the "cohort of being", is typified within psychoanalytic theoretical statements themselves. It is crucial to note that this theoretical operation is not only external to the clinical practice of the discourse of the analyst, but also that it conditions the separation of the analyst's discourse from the rest of discourse. For what could the deliberate intent to subvert the 'dominating discourse' that symptomatically evinces an instance of phantasy in analysis mean for someone who is addressing the psychoanalytic community itself? From which position of enunciation could the theoretical statements of psychoanalysis be issued from, if it is neither a form of the presumed neutrality of objective knowledge proper to University discourse, but neither an instance for the discourse of the analyst? What could psychoanalysis claim to be doing if, as Lacan has repeatedly insisted, there is no meta-language, and if "there is no Other of the Other? " (Ibid; L16, pp. 206).  Yet if knowledge of desire can be obtained or localized from the vantage point of psychoanalytic theory, there seems nothing to keep the philosopher from claiming that what Lacan is doing is effectively ontologizing desire and thus the subject of the unconscious as the libidinal variant of the realm of appearances, and that therefore Lacan has merely supplanted philosophy and psychology with its own prescriptive ideational framework, apt for empirical investigation, i.e. the realm of the unconscious that is "structured like a language"[18].

         Indeed, Lacan himself seems to have been aware of this crucial paradox within his theoretical register from very early on. In what I take to be a decisive statement, Lacan claims with regards to the conceptual status of the psychoanalytic theoretical endeavor: "There is a fundamental ambiguity in the use we make of the word 'desire'. Sometimes we objectify it- and we have to do so, if only to talk about it. On the contrary sometimes we locate it as the primitive term, in relation to any objectification." (S2, pp. 225) This ambiguity is not trivial whatsoever. For if desire must be objectified in order to be spoken about, in what sense is it any different than any of the other terms that philosophers or scientists purportedly use to describe phenomena of all kinds, desire included? How are we to understand the claim that desire is simultaneously of the order of signifier and that which conditions any objectification whatsoever? How to address the Real of the libidinal subject and its Real of the object if, like Zizek insists, "There is no ontology of the Real: the very field of ontology, of the positive order of Being the Real are mutually exclusive: The Real is the immanent blockage or impediment of the order of being, what makes the order of Being inconsistent..." (LTN; Pg. 958).

         This problem is particularly acute: Lacan insists that desire cannot be ontologised. But then what is it that psychoanalytic theory is doing when they 'objectify' desire "if only to speak of it"? How could such an act constitute anything but the making of an ontological valence? Despite his precautions, by flattening the symbolically enveloped epistemological relation between knowing individual and known object into the relation between the Real of the unconscious subject and the impossible object, Lacan seems to be effectively ontologizing the relation between the desire and its object-cause. The deflection of the transcendental relation between words and things at the level of the symbolic is coupled to a reification of the relation between the desiring subject and desired object, at the point where the Reality of both becomes indiscernible.  The Real of desire appears thereby as the ontologization of the relation between the Real subject and the Real object, as the distinction between them becomes a nullity.

        Yet to claim that desire is not just one more signifier in the commerce of the symbolic, but rather the enabling condition for signification and objectivation, is once again to reactivate the relation between signifier and signified, only this time in terms of desire as Real precondition for objects understood as linguistically individuated posits.  In other words, although Lacan has done away with the transcendental relation of reference at the level of the symbolic, he must still covertly depend on the connection between the Real of desire as condition of possibility for the symbolic individuation of the signifier. This is to covertly ontologise desire as an Aristotelian 'first mover', as the 'ground of being', as Ineffable Being stripped even of the honor of the name. And since symbolic objectification occurs on condition of the Real unobjectifiable cause, it follows that even the theory of desire, that psychoanalysis purports to advance, is conditioned on separation between the claims and formulas about desire, and desire itself.  In other words, if Lacan claims that the objectification of desire relates to a pre-objectified desire, then he has reactivated the referential relation between signifier and signified, sign and referent, in the dichotomy between objectual desire-for-us and unobjectifiable desire-in-itself. This surrenders Lacan to a bizarre, libidinal paradox of Kantianism. But to do that he must once again rehabilitate not just the ontological valence of desire as such, but the epistemological valence of the relation between desire's objectification in language and the depths of the desire that it bridges us to in the act of theorizing it, that is, in the making of claims and formulas that express it or which are about it. It is impossible to understand Lacan's claim that desire is a 'precondition' for its objectification unless one reenacts this philosophical cunning of the original psychoanalytic coup against philosophy and science.

           Alternatively, Lacan can insist that the objectification in question needs of no such relation, and consistently maintain that the signifier "desire" is, like every other, merely in relation to other signifiers, but never aiming towards anything like an ontologically generative 'in-itself'. Thus the terms of psychoanalysis would escape the faith of standing as signifiers for signifieds, and so avoid tacitly playing the role of a 'meta-language'. Indeed, this is what at some point Lacan himself seems to want to claim when he says that "Desire emerges just as it becomes embodied in speech, it emerges with symbolism." (SII, pp. 234). In this reading, the original ambiguity is resolved in favor of a pure objectification of something which, strictly speaking, does not preexist the act of objectification itself.

          Nevertheless, this raises the question about how there could ever be a theory of desire (indeed of anything) having done away with the Real. Without distinguishing how its theoretical statements fulfill a descriptive role without becoming one more instance of the University discourse, but neither falling into the other three forms of discourse, this route ultimately undermines the theoretical status of psychoanalysis. The purported connection to the phenomenon of desire, however enveloped by the signifier, becomes in principle proscribed, and psychoanalysis ends up depriving itself of any authority when describing the subordination of knowledge to desire in theoretical terms. For there could be no categorical distinction between those signifiers that will play the role of "mere signifiers" in their discursive operation according to the four forms, and those of psychoanalytic theory which may unravel their conditions of possibility, lest we return to the philosophical vocation of distinguishing empirical terms from transcendental terms which condition the former, or occupy once again the position of the University discourse by prescribing a kind of knowledge. In the light of such exigency, psychoanalysis must accept that its attempt to objectify desire, if only to speak of it is finally led by the proto-philosophical urgency to know, despite its protestations to the contrary.

          More dramatically, if psychoanalysis cannot validate itself as a theory, neither can the structure of desire it purportedly formalizes and describes as being intractable to knowledge be used to undermine itself in relation to other theories and discourses in general. In other words, psychoanalysis couldn't even surrender its rights to desire without already having 'spoken that which can't be spoken', that is, without already assuming a theoretical position claiming to know of desire as that which slides through everywhere but is nowhere. The result is a fundamental paradox whereby psychoanalysis ceases to be a theory because the exigencies of desire undermine it, and where desire ceases to be the structural phenomenon psychoanalysis describes because the latter is not a theory[19].  Needless to say, this paradox threatens to jeopardize even the clinical practice of psychoanalysis, insofar as once the theoretical valence of its claims and principles have been rendered dubious, so are the practices articulated and prescribed on the basis of those claims and principles suddenly in a precarious position.

          Two scenarios appear possible at his point, as the necessary correctives to psychoanalytic theory. Yet, as we shall see, that the ambiguity of desire as a term and as a condition is ultimately irresolvable. Lacan claimed to have superseded the pretences of philosophy but in turn seems to be forced into the choice between a variant of transcendental idealism and sophistry. The former scenario has itself two possibilities: a) a kind of negative-theological epistemic understanding of the foreclosure of Real desire as that which resists objectification and meaning, and b) a variety of textual idealism where desire is immanent to the signifier, while admitting of a typology of signifiers. Let us assess each of these .       

            First, a possible answer is to leave it open that psychoanalysis may gain traction with respect to Real desire, via the objectification of the signifier. That is, the signifier might grant access to desire as an unknowable, unobjectifiable, but nevertheless thinkable condition of possibility for signification (a variety of 'weak correlationism'[20]). Under this light, Lacan's account of desire as Real precondition begins to startlingly resemble the minimal realism of Heidegger, for whom the opaqueness of the Earth qua unobjectifiable being stands as necessarily refractory to the variegated structure of Worldhood, with its populating entities and individuations at the ontic level. Real desire would be the proto-ontological motor conditioning, ironically, the merely ontic register of being and the symbolic investment of symptoms. The early Lacan seems to indicate this much when he claims in a rather cryptic passage: "Desire... is the desire for nothing namable... this desire lies at the origin of every variety of animation. If being were only what it is there wouldn't be room to talk about it. Being comes into existence as an exact function of this lack." (SII, pp 223). This is the direction in which the later Lacan, through his idea of the Real as that which resists symbolization, seems to have succumbed, as we shall see below[21].

          Alternatively, in this first re-philosophizing scenario, the structure of desire remains epistemically accessible without residue, but confined to the signifying order, in which case Lacan is involved in a bizarre structuralist parody of textual idealism. Yet as we surmised above, this cannot be done, strictly speaking, without a qualitative distinction that vitiates the structural uniformity of the signifier. In other words, it requires a qualitative distinction within the order of the signifier, a typology that sets those signs which map the structure of desire from those which are merely within the libidinal commerce of phantasy, and so those which are theorized by the former in expressing their conditions of possibility. Both options in this scenario rehabilitate the philosophical spooks that Lacan took to have demoted, at the price of reactivating the possibility of a special kind of reference or relation between signifiers, apart from the articulation of the four discourses, and with it one must accept the neutral possibility of attaining the status of a 'meta-language' to save psychoanalytic theory from itself.

        The second alternative, foreclosing the explanatory purchase on desire, and leaving the exteriority of Real desire unthinkable, shuns the status of psychoanalysis as a theory and surrenders it to a sophistic endeavor marking its internal contradiction (a variety of strong correlationism). This is the tragedy that we surmised above, when showing that psychoanalysis couldn't even surrender its rights to knowledge if it fully relinquishes its epistemic vocation, and the possibility of distinguishing between Real desire and its theorization. For in this scenario, the Lacanian edifice ends up undermining itself, rendering the conceptual endeavor it pursues into utter incoherence, the knowledge of desire undermining its theorization, and the theorization of desire undermining the possibility of knowledge of it[22].

         As we suggested above, however, Lacan seems to have progressively realized that he couldn't do without explaining how a theory of Real desire relies on such a conceptual envelopment, as evinced in a particularly telling passage: "[Our] conception of the concept implies that the concept is always established in an approach that is not unrelated to that which is imposed on us, as a form, by infinitesimal calculus. Indeed, if the concept is modeled on an approach to the reality that the concept has been created to apprehend, it is only by a leap a passage to the limit, that it manages to realize itself. We are then required to say in what respect- under what form of finite quantity, I would say- the conceptual elaboration known as the unconscious may be carried out." (SXI: pp. 19) The metaphor is that of an asymptotic approach to the Real via the matheme, forever removed from the concept's touch.

            Yet at this point, signaling both the beginning of a mathematical obsession and that of a poetic escape, Lacan begins to opt for the first horn of the dilemma and to surrender psychoanalysis to what appears under all lights to be a re-philosophizing of its fundamental task, along with the valence of knowing. A passion for the purity of formalization and the inscription, which begins sliding down to the notion that the matheme is closest to the Real. The matheme becomes the receptacle of a pure transmission, insofar as formalization subtracts writing from its conceptual envelopment, prizing it free from any semblance of meaning or intention. This is why, for Lacan, "The mathematical formalization of signifierness runs counter to meaning." (SXX, pp. 93)


The matheme is said to be closest to the Real insofar as it formalizes while symbolizing nothing: it has a Real status insofar as it cannot be positivized in a representation. The Real subtracts itself from all positive content and all imaginary-symbolic envelopments; it is delivered only to the pure act of transmission, the transference of the analyst's intervention which opens the promise for the traversal of the phantasy. Just like the subject, there can be thus no theoretical knowledge of the Real: the latter cannot be totalized or unified by a predicate, or thought of consistently through definable properties. Therefore, it cannot be qualitatively determined so as to be tractable conceptually: "If there is a notion of the real, it is extremely complex and, because of this, incomprehensible, it cannot be comprehended in a way that would make an All out of it."[23] What formalization enables, Lacan wants to say, is not a representation of desire and so of a knowledge about the Real, but rather an experience or 'act' with respect the Real, a possibility for transference in analysis: "Truth cannot convince, knowledge becomes act.[24]" (Ibid; Pg. 104)   

          And yet, as we saw, as much as the matheme itself remains recalcitrant to the symbolic, it is just as true that Lacan cannot dispense of the task of deploying the matheme to formalize psychoanalytic concepts and structures. Lacan himself says that the formalization is the formalization of the signifier: of whatever is articulated through the signifier, psychoanalytic claims included. But if mathematics can operate to formalize psychoanalysis, this is because formalization operates over the concepts and claims that psychoanalysis deploys. But in order for psychoanalytic claims and concepts to be any more apt for the formalization which 'touches the Real' of desire, then the claims of psychoanalysis must be in some respect different than all others; or else the formalization would appear arbitrarily dependant on a discursive register. Yet the on what methodological grounds could we assess whether psychoanalytic enjoy this priority, if not epistemological or semantic?

         At this juncture, the claim that the matheme resists translation is merely to refuse to explain how it is that it functions as a formalization adequate to the statements of psychoanalysis, and which concern the Real as much as the symbolic or the imaginary. The matheme is said not to obey the norms of knowledge or enter into the rule of the symbolic, but at the same time is coordinated with a series of theoretical interpretations, granting it rights before the Real. But what grounds this proximity between the matheme and the Real, as regulated by psychoanalytic concepts? Without explaining this connection, psychoanalysis fails to adequately account for the relation between the practice of formalization and the theoretical statements which provide the semantic interpretation for the mathematical formulas. For the psychoanalyst needs not only the matheme which is recalcitrant to meaning, but a series of theoretical claims explaining how the matheme formalizes certain structures. Without this connection, any mathematical inscription cannot count as the formalization of anything, is truly 'meaningless', and there would be nothing to distinguish pure mathematical forms from Real psychic structures[25]. This would render psychoanalysis complicit with a kind of Pythagorean upsurge. Just like unobjectifiable desire was 'objectified' in theory only to speak of it, the Real non-translatability of the matheme is translated by psychoanalytic theory since, without such a theorization, the matheme could not stand for the formalization of anything whatsoever. The interesting paradox is therefore that although in order for the matheme to be non-translatable to any discursive register that operates under the symbolic it must, paradoxically, be able to be translated into the conceptual register of psychoanalysis, for the latter provides the interpretation without which, the abstract terms would fail to account for anything.

         What this evinces is that psychoanalysis ultimately is forced to speak of the Real ambiguously: in one sense it said to pertain to formalization in its untranslatable dimension, and in another to desire as the unobjectifiable condition for any discourse. It is precisely at this juncture that the unobjectifiable Real of desire, touched only in the act of transference, is mediated by a tacit separation from the matheme that ordains it, evincing a division that psychoanalysis ultimately cannot resolve.  Much like for Heidegger Being qua the unobjectifiable opaqueness of the Earth cannot be apprehended conceptually but must be delivered to the poetic word of the thinker and the act of the artist, the Real qua unobjectifiable opaqueness of desire cannot be known but must be delivered to the epistemic opaqueness of the matheme and the transference occasioned by the analyst in act. As Lacan puts it: "Mathematization alone reaches a real - and it is in that respect that it is compatible with our discourse, with analytic discourse- a real that has nothing to do with what traditional knowledge has served as a basis for, which is not what the latter believes it to be- namely, reality, but rather phantasy... The Real, I will say, is the mystery of the speaking body, the mystery of the unconscious." (SXX; pp. 131)

          However, the call for the bodily act signals also the inevitable moment of loss for explanation, the moment in which, no longer capable of separating the thought of the Real from the Real itself, one must surrender all theoretical pretences and en-act the traversal itself, a clinical pilgrimage before the inflections of the symptom through the lessons of formalization. The discursive access to knowing-that becomes delivered to the oblique efficacy of  non-discursive know-how. This is how we should coordinate these two seemingly disparate statements from Lacan: "There is some rapport of being that cannot be known" (SXX, pp. 119, TM), and "If analysis rests on a presumption, it is that knowledge about [subjective] truth can be constituted on the basis of its experience" (Ibid, pp. 91). The impossibility of a knowledge of being is but the obverse of the possibility of knowing how to speak in bringing about the transference. Or as Badiou formulates it: "The paradoxical position of Lacan concerning truth is that there is no knowledge of truth, but finally there is a psychoanalytic knowledge concerning this absence of knowledge. This is the great paradox of the unconscious...a subject can have an experience of its proper Real only in the form of an act." (Badiou, 2010)


       The levels must be clearly demarcated: the analytic transference enjoins the traversal of the phantasy and is supported by the formalization of the symbolic by the matheme. But as we have seen, the operation of formalization which demarcates the positions and structures is in turn supported by the conceptual register of psychoanalytic theory itself. Lacan can thus claim that: "It is in the very act of speaking that makes this formalization, this ideal meta-language, ex-sist." (SXX, Ibid; pp 119) The two Reals glare forth in their unresolved difference: the pure form of the mathematic inscription, recalcitrant to incorporation within the symbolic order of language, and Real of desire in the passage to the pure act that deposes all representational knowledge, where the traversal of the phantasy takes place. As Badiou stresses: "This act is like a cut in language and also a cut in the ordinary representation of the world- a representation which is imaginary. So the act suddenly isolates the Real from its normal collection to the imaginary and symbolic orders." (Badiou, 2010).


              And yet we must insist, that for all its purported deflection of knowing-that, the abyss that separates the Real voided matheme from the Real of desire merely reproduces the dyad of signifier/signified in the dichotomy between theoretical inscription and practical transmission. That is, Lacan reproduces the problem between thought and reality that he takes to be emblematic of the philosophical forms of 'knowing' in the tacit distinction between the formal ideography of the matheme in its presentation, and the singular act of speech in which transference finally takes place and Real desire 'moves'. For Lacan cannot conflate the speciousness of the formulaic writing of the matheme with the act of speech through which the subject traverses the phantasy, nor with the desire in the subject itself. That this distinction is ultimately unexplainable, that the connection between the Real qua formalized matheme and the Real qua act cannot be justified but merely presupposed by psychoanalysis, reveals the latter's internal gulf, delivered as it is, both to the requirement to forego knowledge, and yet also to ordain it by yielding knowledge of its own.  This separation ultimately makes the status of the Real undecidable, or fatally ambiguous, i.e. playing the role of a pure inscription without exteriority (the Real of the matheme as formalization), or a pure exteriority without symbolization (the Real is that which resists symbolization). With the Real subtracted from the traction of knowing, it becomes a noumenal phantasm suspended between the void of an empty formalism, or a mystical surrender to the ineffable Otherness that animates the act.


               And so one notes also, alongside the obliqueness of the matheme, a desperation against the threat of the "dialectic" and a helplessness evinced toward the poetic rumination, thinking from a distance the untouchable purity of an Otherness so unblemished that it does nothing but subtract itself from the signifier and its operations. Such is the sliding down to the identification of the Real with that which is ultimately beyond all capacity for individuation, rendering the conditioning of the Real of desire excised from its pseudo-objectifications[26]. Unfortunately then, the question about the legitimacy of desire as a suitable structure to explain to ontogenesis of thought and being, returns into the market of theories negotiating an unnamable void for their founding gesture. Perhaps this is why Lacan struggles, refusing to fully embrace the prospect of ontologizing the unconscious and desire, to the point of reverting into the desperation of sophism: "the gap of the unconscious is pre-ontological... it is neither being nor non-being, but the unrealized." (SXI: pp. 29)

            We hear echoes of Heidegger's attempts to reconcile himself with his own theory, trying to save the Great Outdoors from the clutches of Dasein's world-producing prerogative (claiming animals have and do not have worlds by saying they are 'poor in them', for instance). Lacan, scavenging for the Real, this being without the honor of the name, urges the separation between psychoanalysis and philosophy, much like for Heidegger poetic thought could only free itself by separating itself from the loudness of metaphysics. A scission, to be sure, that appears as the uncompromising desire for desire, stubbornly clinging to its own impossible object, its own unrequited passion. For the Real does not speak, after all, putting an end to the disguised epistolary confession of the philosopher and the scientist, as well as the analysand. Is this not where the tormented psychoanalyst geared towards the interruption of the symptom by the act and the matheme, and the disillusioned  provincialism of the poetic philosopher traversing metaphysics through poetry meet again: in the desire for silence?

         Ultimately, the Real anchor of desire and its object, this 'indivisible remainder', does not absolve Lacan from the faith of the philosophical dictum, but rather delivers him back into what Badiou has called 'the effects of skepticism': "The effects of this kind of frenzied upsurge, in which the real rules over the comedy of our symptoms, are ultimately indiscernible from those of skepticism.[27]" (LOW: Pg. 563) And indeed, I think Badiou is correct here: Lacan's cryptic statement from 1977 that "truth can only concern the Real" is perhaps the point of the unique symptom, the torsion where, suspended between the choice between being and nothingness, Lacan nods for the all-too-familiar philosophical maneuver, and proceeds to identify them. The sliding void of the object names the passion for the unnamable stain that, repudiating the stringency of the symbolic demand, refuses to extirpate itself from thought, however elusive to its feeble touch. The Real nothingness of Being, and so philosophy, appears now as the stain for psychoanalysis, refusing to let the words come to an end. That is, without ever traversing its own fantasy, absolving the tormented analyst from his own confessional delirium.


Index of Abbreviations
E = Ecrits
SII: Seminar II
SIII: Seminar III
SVI: Seminar VI
SXX: Seminar XX
SXI: Seminar XI





[1] The attempt to define and restrict the scope of the thinkable in terms of fixed categorical determinations already presupposes the libidinal core of the subject as void of any content, as it passes through the experience of alienation by becoming integrated into language: "If what Freud discovered, and rediscovers ever more abruptly, has a meaning, it is that the signifier’s displacement determines subjects’ acts, destiny, refusals, blindnesses, success, and fate, regardless of their innate gifts and instruction, and irregardless of their character or sex; and that everything pertaining to the psychological pre-given follows willy-nilly the signifier’s train, like weapons and baggage" (E, Pg. 30)

[1] This explains Jacques -Alain Miller's formulation apropos Lacan's teachings during 1955 under the title "From the small to the big Other", which also marks Lacan's more pronounced reworking with the structuralist tradition in linguistics, and thus with the problematic of language in general.
[1] It is clear that, at least in the 1950's, Lacan's concept of the unconscious is deeply influence by the Hegelian-Kojevian notion of desire as the desire of recognition of the other.
[1]
[1] Seminar XX, p.50

[1] This structure is simultaneously that which provides thus the condition for consciousness as consciousness of something, and that which eludes the explicit 'aboutness' of conscious intentionality.  It is insofar that the subject constitutes its unconscious as a result of this alienating operation of 'symbolic castration' that the latter is not a mere myth to be allotted alongside the inventions of philosophers and psychologists alike: “...what is not a myth, although Freud formulated it just as early on as he formulated the Oedipus myth, is the castration complex” (E; Pg. 695).

[1] More subtly, it attempts to find within the signifying chain itself those symptomatic points of capture and torsion, the anomalies and ruptures which locate the subject’s unconsciously articulated desire, i.e. its metonymic points of torsion and articulation. Thus Lacan emphasizes the “…the radical role of metaphor and metonymy, substitution and combination of signifiers in synchronic and diachronic dimensions" (Ibid).
[1] - Seminar XX, p.50

[1] Indeed, the word "ontology" is not mentioned once in Seminar VI.

[1] For the development on the four discourses, see especially Seminar XII, Norton 2007.

[1] It is obvious at this point that Lacan cannot mean that the unconscious is determined by a language, since this would make it a kind of signified upon which the signifier would work. Rather, the unconscious is the very process of signification: You see that by still preserving this ‘like’ [comme], I am staying within the bounds of what I put forward when I say that the unconscious is structured like a language. I saylike so as not to say – and I come back to this all the time – that the unconscious is structured by a language. The unconscious is structured like the assemblages in question in set theory, which are like letters" Seminar XX, p.48 (Edited by Jacques-Alain Miller, W.W. Norton, 1999) Although the appeals to set theory here are obviously metaphoric, they point to the idea, emphasized by Badiou that, just like sets are not multiples of anything, language is not of the unconscious; the latter would be to reconstitute the relation between signifier and signified that Lacan is in the process of dismantling. 
[1] MEILLASSOUX, Quentin, After Finitude, translated by Ray Brassier, Continuum, 2006.

[1] Roughly, from Seminar XI onwards.

[1] Even if we agree with Badiou that psychoanalysis is indeed closer to politics in seeking the singularity of the individual symptom rather than the repetition of the scientific thought, it must be stressed that, irrespective of the clinical practice, the theoretical endeavor carried out by psychoanalytic thought cannot but be subject to the norms of conceptual consistency which binds scientific thought. If this is the case, then the way that psychoanalysis shields itself against the dogmatism of embracing alienation in the signifier to its fullest extent would not be to simply listen to the 'affirmative' vocation of political thought, but also to the scientific vocation for what renders its theoretical posits possible, i.e. formal coherency of its ideography.

[1] Lacan, J., Le triomphe de la religion, précedé du Discours aux catholiques, Paris: Seuil 2005, p. 96, 97.

[1] Accordingly, the object-cause of desire as a Real is thought through the formalization of a vanishing object, non-identical to itself, always alienating the subject from the place of enunciation.  This is why the phallus, as the mask hiding the displacement of the object, constitutes the metonymy of the subject in being: the object of desire is 'subjectivized' insofar as it refuses to ever coincide with the phallic semblances under which it appears or is formulated. This 'becoming subject of substance', to speak Hegelese, is what makes the meaningless formalism 'nearest' to the Real object and so to the unconscious desire.

[1] This is why Zizek calls "the scientific Real" that  "...of a formula which renders the nature's meaningless functioning." (Zizek, How to Read Lacan, http://www.lacan.com/zizalien.htm)

[1] It is not only the structure of unconscious desire that is beyond recalcitrant to ontology: the object of desire itself is, paradoxically, unobjectifiable insofar as it remains impossible, non-self identical, never coincident with a  being with fixed qualities and properties. This indicates another level of the fundamental coincidence between the non-symbolic inscription of the object, and the object itself. This is because objet a is both resolutely material (it is localized) and a formal index signaling that which is never localizable, but which functions as an impasse for meaning, and so which indexes the asymptotic horizon of the subject's intentional desire. The object of desire is neither being (it resists objectification or self-identity, thus enacting the infinity of  subjective desire) nor non-being (it must nevertheless be indexed as impossible object cause, 'if only to speak of it', as that which consists as inconsistent, subtracting itself from the signifying chain).  The Real object can only be Real insofar as it is also, and paradoxically, a 'non-object', that is, insofar as it is on the side of the formal stringency of the matheme and not of the symbolic-imaginary operations of the signifier. Only the pure matheme approaches it in its barren formalism by ordaining it to the act of analytic transference facilitating the traversal of the phantasy: "[Objet a] would have us take it for being, in the name of the following- that it is apparently something. But it only dissolves, in the final analysis, owing to its failure, unable, as it is, to sustain itself in approaching the real." (SXX: Pg. 95)

[1] In this regard, I would emphasize that, in spite of Badiou's commendable attempts to characterize psychoanalysis as a candidate for thinking but perhaps not a science, where the latter term is understood as "the unity of a theory and a practice", does not help solve the issue. This can be easily seen if we realize that the incapacity to separate theory and practice is not something we can straightforwardly allot to science; even if psychoanalysis is thought as closer to politics, the question about the relation between the statements of such a thought and the thing itself remains. To stipulate an absolute inseparability between thought and world is to surrender to idealism; to claim such a distinction is possible is to rehabilitate the valence of knowing within a philosophical thought. I believe, for reasons that Ray Brassier has pointed out, following Wilfrid Sellars, that the methodological separation between the space of reasons and the space of causes is the condition of possibility for the ontological unity between thought and being, reason and nature. The consequence, against Badiou's depiction, is not a thinking of the articulation between a theory and a praxis, but rather how such an articulation is to be understood as that between world that is not thought and thought that thinks the world.

jueves, 30 de agosto de 2012

Žižek Against Brassier: On Conditions for Realism


Žižek Against Brassier:

- On Conditions for Realism -

______________________________

       In Less Than Nothing,  Žižek  attempts to defend his Lacanian position as being the most cogent realist alternative, while challenging Brassier's older Laruelle-inspired account. His basic claim is that the question of realism as formulated by Meillassoux remains encumbered in the transcendental problematic of how one's inner world represents external reality, while the only true materialism requires objectifying thought by making the subject coincide with the Real, or in other words, to account for how reality 'appears to itself'. So far so good; things seem fairly congruent with the unilateralization that Laruelle himself pursues. But the argument he offers for the Lacanian option is, well, very sloppy. The first crucial passage is the following one:

      "The difference between Brassier's position and the Lacano-Hegelian position can be summed up by a simple replacement: Brassier refers to Freud's triple de-centering or humilliation of man's narcissism- Copernicus, Darwin, psychoanalysis- but he replaces psychoanalysis with cognitivism. The latter fully naturalizes our mind, reducing it to a phenomenon arising out of evolution- but perhaps Brassier proceeds too fast here: while cognitivism de-centers the human mind from outside, treating it as an effect of objective natural mechanisms only psychoanalysis de-centers it from within, revealing how the human mind involves not only objective neuronal processes which are inaccessible to it."

    It goes without saying that Zižek  here misidentifies Brassier's position with a neurophysiological reductionism, or eliminativist materialism. It's already a bit remarkable that Zizek would attribute this position to Ray, when the latter's argument vis a vis the eliminativist project of the Churchlands is pointing out its conceptual incoherence. And needless to say, Brassier's new Sellarsian position goes rather well with the idea that subjectivity has a dimension that is irreducible to causal, objective processes. This is, as we know, precisely the separation that Sellars proposes to make, following Kant, between reasons and causes: subjectivity is defined not metaphysically, but functionally in terms of the capacity of exhibiting intentional behavior, i.e. the capacity to undertake normative statuses by entering the 'logical space of reasons'. According to this conception of subjectivity, although the neurophysiological provides the ontological substratum for sapience, it is only insofar as the latter entails rational subjectivation that one comes to know of the former. In other words, while there is an ontological priority of the logical on the causal (there would not be thought without the proper biophysical evolutionary conditions obtaining; purposiveness arises out of purposeless mechanisms), there is an epistemological priority of the causal on the rational (only sapient creatures that inhabit the space of reasons can undertake normative statuses, and commit themselves to claims).



       Accordingly, Brassier proposes in terms of the distinction between phenomenal consciousness and rational subjectivity, the former being the illusory projection of a unitary self-model which is causally explainable in terms of the functional role of our neurophysiological system, while the latter provides the irreducible dimension wherein we understand the necessary concepts for concept-attribution and revision: justification, entitlement, belief, commitment, evidence, etc. Provisionally we might say then that psychoanalysis is not, contrary to what  Žižek   suggests, the only option that 'de-centers' thought 'from within', since Sellarsian nominalism also describes the internal conditions required for any empirical explanation or for indeed an investigation of facts, i.e. Sellars emphasizes that the capacity to make claims or have beliefs about what it the case requires that we know have to use modal notions, i.e. in order to believe or know that the cat is on the mat we need to be able to separate what inferentially follows from being a cat from that which doesn't. Thus, fact-stating or objective discourse logically depends on modal talk about what ought-to-be the case, and so it requires natural necessity, as well as pragmatic necessity (we need to know what we are committed to by having beliefs about cats as opposed to something else, and this obligation is to be understood in terms of proprieties for action in the making of inferences, observation reports, and action).
     But while the structuralist and the nominalist seem to coincide in their preservation of an irreducible dimension of subjectivity, whether rational-procedural or libidinal-symptomal, they disagree with respect to the role, if any, reserved for the transcendental conception of subjectivity. 



       Brassier, like Sellars, conceives of his nominalism as not only compatible with but as the condition for a naturalist metaphysics. However immanent to his semantic nominalism, the functional conception of subjectivity thus proposed is still transcendental. Sellarsian philosophy is not transcendental in the strong sense in which it gives the conditions for how mind or language 'reaches out into world', but in the weak sense in which rational norms provide the transcendental conditions for any empirical investigation of objective processes. The irreducibility of the normative is thereby methodological and epistemological, not metaphysical. Representation being a function of conceptual role in an inferentially-articulated linguistic economy, Sellarsian nominalism refuses the reification of intuition as a kind of subjectively constituted species of representation, of the sort that would wrap the correlationist leash around the mind by keeping the great outdoors proscribed from our reach. 



     Žižek , in turn, wants to liquidate the mediating function of epistemological knowing, and of linguistic 'rationality' as the core of the subject, the better to safeguard a purely voided conception of the subject which is less than ontological, which means also less than transcendental. This is of course because Zizek understands the transcendental problematic of access as still encumbered in a pre-Hegelian stage, which is overcome by asking about the emergence of real appearing as opposed to the separation between reality and appearance. So as to avoid the reduction of subjectivity to objectivity without reifying subjectivity metaphysically,  Žižek  searches for a purely formal conception of Real subjectivity.


     
The Lacanian story is familiar: the subject 'slides' through the signifiers, as a pure functional index that operates invisibly, at the point in which formal inscription is indiscernible from Real phenomenon. The matheme adequate to the psychoanalytic theorization of the Real desire subtracts itself from the commerce of the symbolic, undergirding the delirium of the phantasy and the symptom with its structural universality, i.e. its irreducibility and ubiquity. And this impossibility of translating the mathematic inscription of the subject into any positive, qualitatively specific, philosophical register, is supposed to wrest any sort of ontological baggage from its pretenses.



   At this juncture, the second quote compendium from Žižek, in alleged agreement with Laruelle, makes the Lacanian position apropos realism very slippery:



   " [T]he problem is not how to think the in-itself without mind, but how to think the 'objectual' status of this zero point of thinking itself...[T]he very distance which separates us from the In-itself is immanent to the In-itself, makes us (the subject) an unaccountable/"impossible" gap or cut within the in-itself. Insofar as, for Lacan, "what is foreclosed to thought in the object" is the "impossible" objet a, and "what is foreclosed to the object in thought" is $, the void of the barred subject itself, this overlapping brings us back to Lacan's formula $-a

     ... The Lacanian Real-impossible is precisely such a 'given without givenness', without a phenomenological horizon opening the space for it to appear, the impossible point of the ontic without the ontological... What we call 'external reality' (as a constituent field of already existing objects) arises through subtraction, that is, when something is subtracted from it- and that something is the objet a. The correlation between subject and object (objective reality) is thus sustained by the relation between the same subject and its objectual correlate, the impossible-Real objet a, and this second correlation is of a totally different kind: it is a kind of negative correlation, an impossible link, a non relationship, between two moments that can never meet within the same space... not because they are too far away, but because they are one and the same entity on the two sides of a Mobius band. This impossible-Real virtual object is not external to the symbolic but its immanent impediment, what makes this symbolic space curved... What this means, in effect, is that there is no ontology of the Real: the very field of ontology, of the positive order of Being the Real are mutually exclusive: The Real is the immanent blockage or impediment of the order of being, what makes the order of Being inconsistent... 

         Lacan is not a discourse idealist who claims that we are forever caught in the web of symbolic practices, unable to reach the In itself. However, we do not touch the Real by way of breaking out of the prison of language and gaining access to the external transcendent referent- every external referent ("fully existing positive reality") is already transcendentally constituted. We touch the Real-in-itself in our very failure to touch it, since the Real is, at its most radical, the gap, the "minimal difference", that separates the One from itself." (Pg. 954-9)

   I find  Žižek's ruminations here to be profoundly unpersuasive, even confused. To see why it is simple enough to realize that for all his defenses against the charge of idealism-correlationism, the conception of the Real provided here is still correlational, however reduced to formal aspects, and however much  Žižek wants to say that the Real 'resists ontology'. 


     Put simply: if the reality commensurate with ontology is epiphenomenal and the Real is its non-ontologizable "ontic residue", then 
Žižek has bought into the idea that the Real is indeterminate categorically, an ineffable remainder, forcing us to render the objective status of our that which our claims are about and our ontological valences merely for-us. This is the typical move which renders the Real almost like a negative-theological pole. The theory of the Real 'desire' cannot be ontology, because the world of ontology is relative to the commerce of the symbolic and the signifier, underwritten only by the formal vacuity of unconscious desire.


     More crucially, the Real
objet a is described as that which alongside the subject cannot be positivized, but for which nevertheless the subject remains its condition of possibility. Yet here is where the realist must pull the breaks. The question of the Real is not just that of a gap between the subject and its object, or the gap in subjectivity itself. No! The question about the Real is, as Meilassoux and Brassier insist, and contra Žižek, that of a world radically indifferent to thought.


   Dissolving the transcendental, 
Žižek  cannot but end up conflating the epistemological and the ontological, and so sense dependence and reference dependence. To remind ourselves of this crucial distinction:
1) Sense dependence - For any x, x is sense dependent on y iff x cannot be known unless y is known.
2) Reference-dependence: For any x, x is reference dependent on y iff x cannot exist unless y exists.


       The result of this is that the fear of thinking that knowledge of an external reality requires vitiating the immanent account of language in favor of an old 'mirror theory', is unfounded. Sellars' contention is to preserve an immanent understanding of semantics in his nominalism, while refusing to say that, because language is the condition for knowing, all ontological valences or claims must be ontologically for-us as well, leaving us with a barren conception of the Real as the impossible inconsistency of being, however lacking the honor of the name.


     We must insist that while the categorical specificity of the object as thought is 
epistemologically relative to a subject, this is not to say its being is dependent on a subject. The question anyone should address to  Žižek is simple: can one think of the Real object as not just the zero-point of thinking or its correlative object, but as that which requires no thinking at all for its being? The problem is that eliding the epistemological and ontological levels, along the Hegelian identification of logic and metaphysics, one cannot but claim that logical dependency is metaphysical dependency. But to deny the possibility of categorical determination in being is to continue to reify being as an ineffable chimera, or impossible inconsistency, reducing the phenomenal determinacy of the world to being subjective constructs. And to continue to claim that the Real is a function of the subject's emergence, as that which subtracts itself from every positive valence, is still to be a correlationist, or an idealist even. Indeed, if it makes no sense to speak of a Real that precedes ontologically the emergence of the subject, even if the latter conditions its epistemic appearing, one begins to sound like a strange proto-creationist according to which the emergence of mind occasions the Real as a byproduct or splitting. 



   At this point it seems clear that, eliding the transcendental, Žižek, like Lacan, just has no resources to distinguish between the Real subject and its Real object ($<>a) in such a way so as to avoid reifying the relation between the two ontologically, neverming his protests to the contrary. This seems to be the result of every attempt at eliding the referential relation between knower and known: it becomes impossible to distinguish between the thinking of the Real and the Real itself, since by proposing a formal conception of the Real in which the vacuity of the subject is knit to its objective polarity, any criterion of distinction between the two becomes a nullity. Just like in Badiou's endorsement of the Parmenidean thesis, the matheme 'touches' the Real and the subject its impossible objectual pole insofar as it cannot distinguish itself from it, since any such positive delineation involves a pathological ontologizing of the difference between thought and the object, like transcendental correlationism is imputed to do. 



     But the price to be paid for this destitution of epistemology is the inability to explain the distinction between the Real inscription of the matheme which formalizes the Real's structure apart from the commerce of the symbolic, and the Real phenomenon or the voided subject-object gap, which subtracts itself from all ontology. There are thus three gaps:


- Between the Symbolic and the Real.
- Between the Real Object and the Real Subject
- Between Real inscription or matheme and the Real of the object/subject as such.


The incapacity to distinguish being from thought is the inevitable consequence of trying to wrest the Real from the symbollic by making the latter not just epistemologically constrictive, but ontologically afoul. Against the drama of the void which, however proud of its formal stringency, remains the gulf for a residual romantic fideism, we must insist on the difference between knower and known, between sign and referent, as that which provides the conditions to separate mind and world.

If the Real cannot be understood as ontologically autonomous from the subject, then dialectical materialism proves to be just another correlationism or idealism, one in which the Real is the non-ontologizable intrusion of that which, however recalcitrant to the Word, glares forth in its formal presence without remainder.

lunes, 20 de agosto de 2012

The Destruction and Reconstitution of Experience: On Sellars' Account of Ur-Conceptuality and Sensibility



THE DESTRUCTION AND RECONSTITUTION OF EXPERIENCE:
On Sellars, Sensibility and Correlationism
__________________________________

   

    I have been re-considering Sellars' account of "ur-conceptuality" from the Lever of Archimedes in the Carus Lectures, after evaluating my contention, presented during the Bonn summer school about a month ago, that these are not to be understood in terms of 'pre-linguistic' cognitive capacities, but are rather more like 'rudimentary concepts', already linguistically mediated, if not fully functional in the logical space of reasons.  In what follows I intend to present this issue which, I believe, ties up some essential knots on the questions about the relationship between Sellars' nominalism and his realist metaphysics.



1. Ur-Concepts and Primitive Representation
           In a discussion with Roderick Firth, Sellars sets out to separate the primitive conceptual capacity of pre-adult humans to discern secondary qualities as component-parts of physical objects. He thereby seeks to pin down precisely how it is that appearances already enjoy a primitive ontological status, the better to eventually offer successor concepts in order to supersede not only the base conceptual attributions that children make, but also our available 'adult' concepts for secondary qualities.  The ur-concepts that Sellars attributes to the infant Jones Junior are as follows[1]:


1.       Junior has an ur-concept of volumes and expanses of red stuff.
2.       Junior has an ur-concept of seeing a volume of red stuff.
3.       Junior has an' ur-concept of a physical object as an individuated volume of color stuff which is endowed with certain causal properties.
4.       Junior has an ur-concept of seeing a volume or expanse of red stuff not only as a volume or expanse of red, but as a constituent of a physical object.
5.       Junior has an ur-concept of what it is to see of a physical object a volume or expanse of red which is one of its constituents. If the constituent is the surface of an opaque object, e.g., an apple, it is the very redness of the apple.
6.       Junior has an ur-concept of what it is to see the very redness of an object.


      The problem at hand is what precise status these ur-concepts have; are they linguistic capacities or representations? Or are they another species, perhaps psychological, of intentional representation? What is behind Junior's capacity to do all of these things?


   At Bonn, Ray Brassier flirted with the idea that these might be understood best as pre-linguistic capacities, while I contended the opposite. Essentially, I think my original contention was fundamentally correct, but I think I can see why Sellars' own formulation of the problem might nevertheless tempt us to identify ur-concepts with pre-linguistic capacities, especially judging from what he says in other writings. Moreover, in his influential study, James O'Shea identifies ur-concepts with pre-linguistic capacities, which would seem to settle the case once and for all. I think the issue is more complicated, and ultimately important.


   The two crucial texts that I think help us figure out what's going on, however tentatively, are Some Reflections on Language Games and the Mental Events paper. These will also shed a lot of light into why many consider Sellars' venture into process metaphysics to constitute a relapse into a form of the Myth of the Given, or finally a form of adherence into naturalist prejudices that strictly speaking are 'pre-Sellarsian'. The separation between left and right wing forms of Sellarsianism can be mapped to some of the neighboring issues as well. But anyhow, I think these texts allow us to see why the thesis that ur-concepts are pre-linguistic is infelicitous.



   In Some Reflections on Language Games, Sellars considers the original empiricist or naive realist appeal to pre-linguistic ur-concepts as facilitating the capacity to associate undefined descriptive predicates ('red) with items in the world. The basic idea that these thinkers shared is that the meaning of our observation statements derives from our primitive cognitive capacity to apprehend the categorical structure of the world, and specifically the content concerning perceptible qualities. The subsequent idea was that the predicates involved in observation statements (as paradigmatic ways in which causal stimuli trigger linguistic responses or "language-entry transitions") acquire meaning  as we learn to obey "semantical rules" which in involve recognizing colored things. Say, our concept of 'red things' acquires meaning as we learn to explicitly obey the rule red objects are to be called 'red', and so on. This is not to say, of course, that we need to have a concept of the rule in order to obey it; but that our behavior exhibits conformity to the rule in a sense in which we count as having internalized it, as exhibited by regularities of behavior, and specifically in learning to recognize objects of the right sort. But what grounds the surreptitious pre-linguistic capacity for recognition that subjects make explicit as they learn to deploy observation talk? Sellars critically considers two such candidate accounts for these ur-concepts that allow pre-linguistic categorical apprehension:

1) A symbolic structure or language -  Under this hypothesis, there is a fundamental language or symbolic system that is not itself acquired by obeying rules, but that rather conditions that possibility of identifying different terms in different languages as being about the same thing, beyond their functional role. For if learning to use a concept requires identifying by way of its use an appropriate kind of object/properties or class of objects/properties, then we need to explain how we come to identify such objects or properties of being of that kind.

         If in order to learn the meaning of 'rot' we obey the rule 'red objects are to be called rot' then, in pains of regress, we need to say that the symbolic language by virtue of which we identify 'red objects' is unique, and not itself learned by virtue of obeying a further rule, for this would obviously unchain an infinite regress. This must hold necessarily since obviously the ur-concept of 'red object' would have to be different than the concept we learn by virtue of obeying the semantic rule in which the ur-concept is formulated, in order not to fall to the inconsistent hypothesis that we acquire concepts on condition that we already have them. Thus, some basic language is primitive in the sense that it is not acquired by obeying rules and in that it conditions all further learning by relating the functional role of a term in another language to the objects/properties that we identify primitively in the base language.

 
      It is precisely on the basis of such an ur-conceptual economy we can then learn the functional role that specific linguistic tokens bare to empirical reality, i.e. the contents of descriptive predicates (redness, red items...etc). I think this preemptively anticipates the nativist hypothesis championed by Fodor and Lepore, among others, according to which innate conceptual structures precede and condition that capacity for learning, and thus full-blown linguistic rationality.

2) The capacity to apprehend items as belonging to kinds or resembling classes of particulars  - Sellars castigates this position as a variant of the 'mental eye' view which ascribes to the mind the capacity to immediately apprehend the categorical structure of the physical world, sense qualities, or whatever else, by fixating itself inwardly and outwardly at once. But it seems clear that were Sellars to endorse this, he would be delivered right back into both the matrimonial account of meaning and the epistemological Myth of Given. For it would require postulating both that we have immediate awareness of abstract entities which furnish the categorical structure of reality ('redness'), and that it is by virtue of such awareness that words acquire meaning. But this is to reactivate knowledge by acquaintance.

       At this juncture it becomes clear that the the first, proto-Fodorian hypothesis must also postulate a pre-rational cognitive symbolic economy that simply staples mind into world. But this is another version of the Myth of the Given since, it seems that whatever this system is, it works to grant a sort of luminosity into at least the undefined color qualities of objects.

    It is important to note that in SRLG, Sellars rejects both accounts of pre-linguistic ur-concepts as facilitating the rule obeying usage of observational language. The solution seems to be clear: we have to account for language acquisition not as the explicitation of a semantic protocol for recognizing 'red things' via some dubious 'semantic intuition'. We don't learn to say red because we learn to obey the rule that we should utter 'red' when we see a red thing. For then the ur-conceptual protocol as a foundational discourse is introduced simply to halt the inevitable regress that follows from the thesis that we need a meta-language to learn a language. The obvious alternative thesis is to say that an observation-language is, if not learned as rule-obeying,  a conditioned responsive behavior. We can relax our account to claim that although one does not obey rules to apply observational discourse, one must nevertheless be conditioned to respond to the right sorts of entities in the world. Thus, to say that "...the fact that the word 'red' means the quality red may be identified with the fact that 'red' is a conditioned response to red things" (Sc. 38). But while Sellars accepts that indeed the proper application of the word involves being capable of reliably responding to the occurrent stimuli, he warns against the dubious claim that this entails that words acquire meaning by being associated with things. Reiterating the distinction between acting in accordance to rules and acting in accordance with conceptions of rules, Sellars' suggestion is that in acting in accordance to rules we are simply conditioned to respond to red things in the right circumstances, rather than assigning a term to an object we have already recognized in advance by some prior intentional mechanism. This is obviously a corollary of Sellars idea that there is no form of intentionality that precedes the linguistic; neither psychological nor practical.

       What is going on, then, when Sellars speaks of ur-concepts in Junior's talk?

     Now, it seems tempting to claim that when formulating his account of ur-conceptuality to open the space for the analysis of sensibilia or sensa, Sellars reverts into something like the second variant of the empiricist/ naive-realist account outlined above, in virtue of which we have some kind of immediate awareness of the categorical contents of reality. This might be reinforced by considering that Sellars also wants to account for something like pre-linguistic, "animal representations" or proto-cognitions roughly around the same time as the Carus Lectures, in Mental Events (1981). And yet it seems just implausible that Sellars would have suddenly relapsed into a mind's-eye view, of all people! How are we, then, to account for the ur-conceptual status of Junior's experiencing of sensible qualities as constituents of physical objects?

   I think Sellars' remarks in S. 38 of SRLG point towards the right solution. Although it is true that our we cannot have a concept of red without being capable of reliably responding to instances of red, it does not follow that we must equate the meaning of the word with a relation to an item in the world. We can simultaneously accept that our capacity to use undefined predicate-quality words as conditioned by capacity to differentially respond to environmental stimuli in a way that precedes rational rule-obeying, while maintaining that the meaning of the word is nothing but its role in a conceptual economy. Sensibility itself plays no epistemic role, even if it is necessary to acquire knowledge. Sellars must preserve his nominalist account: meaning is functionally specified within a conceptual economy.

     But this means that Junior's ur-concept of red is not 'pre-linguistic' in the sense that it involves the operations of a nativist ur-language (hypothesis 1), nor the fixation of the mind's eye upon the categorical structure of the given via intellectual intuition or some other pre-linguistic intentional mechanism (hypothesis 2). Junior clearly is conditioned to respond with the verbal output 'red' when he sees red things, and can do so somewhat reliably. He uses language already in a self-conscious manner, even if lacking full fledged capacities to enter into deliberative reason-giving behavior.

          Furthermore, his ur-concept is not one of something looking red, but of something being red, since he lacks the contrastive concepts of 'looks/is' introduced upon further conditioning. Junior attributes the redness he sees to the objects he interacts with rather than to private experiences, fields of sense, or whatnot. This is not to say that Junior has a fully-developed concept of 'physical object, extended in space' at that stage, or something so sophisticated. It's clear Junior is not yet capable to playing the game of giving and asking for reasons, or of using the contrastive concepts of 'looks/is' to enact withdrawal of endorsement, or to characterize episodes as merely ontensible seeings. He reports redness as pertaining to objects, and is flummoxed when some evil grown-up tampers with lighting conditions so that what he takes to be a red object suddenly appears blue.  He must then simply retort to thinking that a blue object is before him, and needs eventual introduction into the contrastive concepts to distinguish between mere seemings/lookings and actual features of objects, by modifying his entitlement towards the content of the claim. Thus, Sellars' 'ur-concepts' are utterly linguistic capacities; they cannot be understood as primitive capacities at the level of mere sentient registration and causal responsiveness. Junior's repertoire is surely already more sophisticated than that.

     So what does then, this ur-concept of redness, encompass? Sellars list is amply clarifying.
  It clearly already involves the capacity to see a red thing as red, or that it is red, since Junior attributes redness to that which he sees. Although Sellars characterizes this as-content as being 'of a physical object' this should be taken in tandem with his qualification in section 32, where he makes it clear that Junior has the notion of an object as a 'determinate thing-stuff'; but not the full-grown concept of physical we attribute to adults and which evidently Junior could not have. This is of a piece with his reductive semantics of sensa that he provisionally already proposed in Some Reflections on Perceptual Consciousness (1975).

 
   Junior also has the capacity to see of the thing the redness which is a extended surface of the object, i.e. Junior is not shocked if when splitting an apple in half the inside of the apple is not red too. Junior sees of the object the facing side, which is non-conceptually given to him through his senses. But having an ur-concept of what it is to see of an object, Junior thus both is capable of attributing redness to the object, and at the same time realizing that this redness pertains to something like the extended surfaces of opaque objects, rather than being a thorough characteristic of objects through and through. This is crucial, since it is the first step towards untethering expanses of sense-qualities from objects; a move that Sellars subsequently exploits for metaphysical speculation. This is what is fundamentally added by conditions (5) and (6).

      Junior's ur-concept of red is thus conditionally acquired and not rule-obeying, linguistic insofar as it involves predicative attributions and the capacity to see things as such-and-such, yet too rudimentary to count as an 'adult concept' since it lacks the contrastive concepts that allows one to formulate one's endorsement or lack thereof, on the basis of warrant tethered to a notion of standard conditions, and so on.  And precisely because Junior's ur-concept of red is simply a 'rudimentary' rather than 'foundational' concept that Sellars can resist the myth of the categorial given: it's not that Junior, before learning language, already accesses the categorical structure of the physical world. Junior is conditioned to respond in ways through which he becomes capable of characterizing the contents of his experience, but this already involves linguistic mediation/acculturation.  Junior has no determinate category of colored physical objects extended in space, he has an determinate concept of something-being-colored as a colored-expanse more generally. This is the only way to reconcile the psychological nominalism with the holistic account of linguistic rationality, I think.

       On this account, it becomes a lot clearer just where the Carus Lectures depart from the account of the Myth of Jones, and the looks-talk analysis. Sellars' eventual supplement to the Myth of Jones is to say that before the contrastive concept of looks, which can be applied to color-qualities as easily as dispositional ones, we have a proto-concept of color-qualities or 'the proper sensibles' characterizing them as constituent parts of physical objects, if not identical with them. There is a positivity of appearance that precedes the epistemic regulation of looks talk, which does require fully grown linguistic rationality or integration in the game of giving and asking for reasons. Understanding this also allows us to understand why looks-talk, when applied to color-concepts or sensible-predicates operates withdrawal of endorsement in the form of ostensible seeings, i.e. to merely see red is not just to refrain from claiming that something is red, but to report on the autonomy of the colored expanse from the properties of the object.  The occurrent properties of sense can thereby be examined positively in a metaphysical account.


2. Against Correlationism 
         On a different but related note, this allows us to see how Sellars is precisely not a correlationist. Correlationism requires three conditions:

1) the sense dependence of objects on concepts,
2) the reference dependence of concepts on sensibility, and
3) the ontological identification of sensibility with subjective appearances. Sellars' trick is to accept the first claim, qualify the second, and reject the third.

       Yes, knowledge of anything requires concepts. This is true, but somewhat trivial. Even people like Tyler Burge think knowledge requires justification of the sort only sapient creatures enjoy. Yes, the empiricist is right in insisting that our concepts and so our knowledge of the world begins in sensible experience. But, against the sense-datum theorist or phenomenalist, this is not to say that there is a reference dependence of concepts on sensibility, but only another form of epistemic dependence. That our knowledge is anchored in the world through sensibility is not to say that all knowledge is of the sensible. This is not to refuse that there is such a thing as sensibility, or to say it cannot be metaphysically investigated. Rather, it is simply to say that sensibility can condition our knowledge of that which is not sensible. We can  investigate the non-apparent structure of appearances as belonging to the domain of physical nature, just like we can investigate the micro-physical constitution of the manifestly described world of middle-sized objects and properties apart from their phenomenological conceptual envelopment. Thus, against (3), it is simply false to equate the content of sensibility with 'subjective appearances', where the latter are understood as self-presenting episodes.

         The properties of sense-qualities, although relative to sentient organisms, are irreducible to the phenomenological categories that furnish our commonsense description of the world. Granted, phenomenology reveals that there is a dimension of appearing that must be accounted for. But this is not to say we are forced into construing appearances as subjective correlates. They can be accounted  at the genetic neurocomputational level in terms of how environmental inputs relate to our cognitive faculties by triggering appropriate neuronal onsets.

          Now, Sellars thinks on top of this you can actually characterize the apparent particularity of sensa as ultimately non-object bound physical phenomena, which have irreducible qualitative properties. Sensa turn out to be features that are objectively constituted only in relation to sentient organisms, but they are no less objective for that. In other words, that sensa are dependent on sentience does not render them subjective in any interesting sense. Again, no basic categorical stratum of the sort phenomenologists fetishize over can hope to undergird the objectivity of the physical within which even appearances are constituted.

     Whether that much is tenable remains an open metaphysical question. But the point is that once we have  defused the ontological equation between sensibility and subjective appearances, both forms of epistemic dependence won't do to motivate correlationism. The link between knowledge and conceptuality, and that between conceptuality and sensibility requires that we investigate precisely how observation statements, qua language entry transitions, are articulated with complex causal mechanisms that relate environment to organism. Even if it turns out that the presentational content of experience is fundamentally tethered to sense-data, this is not to assert that sensibility has an autonomous categorical status apart from the physical, nor that the content of our judgments is reducible to sense data just because we require sense data to make them: we can examine the link between appearance and reality by examining the reality of appearing, refusing the phenomenological hypostasis of the categorical status of subjectivity as foundational, by reintegrating sensibility to physical theory, acknowledging it as our anchor to the world, rather than our solipsistic prison.

lunes, 18 de junio de 2012

The Non-Politics of "The Politics Of": Politics and Economy



THE NON-POLITICS OF "THE POLITICS OF":
Politics and Economy / The Manifest Image and the Scientific Image
__________________________________________

Introduction - Methodological Preliminaries, the Analytic-Continental Division Again, Science and Politics

Levi has been making some interesting comments about the connection between politics, analysis and critique, which devolved in a few responses from my part that might be worthy to integrate into a blog-post of its own. The main comment that triggered the responses was the following one

"It's interesting that discussions about the analytic/continental divide almost never mention politics. Almost nothing can be understood about continental thought and debates without understanding the political horizon upon which it unfolds. The same is not true of analytic thought. You could say analytic thought is dominated by an epistemological telos (truth), whereas continental thought is dominated by an ethico-political telos. These are very different codes or operative distinctions." 

My response proceeded as follows: first, I agree in that politics is much more pervasive in Continental discussions, even where some of its canonical figures didn't write all that much on politics (Heidegger; Bergson...). A similar argument can be said about science in Continental theory. Much of the self-proclaimed 'materialisms' are correlationist hybrids, including Marxist conceptions. Even materiality, when it is accepted in the name of a "materialism", is relativized to 'relations of production', or whatnot. I think the ubiquity of the political is in a sense a consequence of the hegemony of anti-realisms: the contextualization of every philosophical valence transforms ontological-epistemological questions to questions about the ways in which discourse organizes human practice.


This also illuminates why the analytic tradition, when committed to metaphysical and epistemological programs, did not think it necessary to pass through the socio-discursive grinder. Even instrumentalisms and (neo) pragmatism were for the most part restricted to methodological questions about a specific practice, rather than inflating the ubiquity of the political in every affirmative gesture. There's obvious exceptions to both rules.

I think, for my part, that the lesson to be learnt is twofold. For the Continentals, the concept of materiality needs to be dislodged from its residual humanism, as made visible when reducing it to 'relations of production'. The materiality of practice is still too anthropomorphically sealed. Any contemporary Marxism that seeks to be truly materialist cannot be encumbered by such a parochial notion. Any stringent concept of revolution to follow cannot continue to avow the heroic revolutionary elan, while keeping economy, techno-scientific insight subordinate to the classical dynamics of class struggle. This kind of weakness leads to thinkers like Badiou being able to claim for example that economy is just the State, and that politics is rather where subjective decision takes place. I think Land is right to mock this romantic exuberance.

For analytics, I think it's clear that the purported realism of their metaphysical positions came at a price of political naivete, which undermined their pretences. Brassier shows this in Nihil Unbound apropos the Churchlands for example, and I think Graham and others show a similar result in Ladyman and Ross, where appeals to the authority of science subordinate realism to pragmatism, and therefore end up becoming victims of a tacit political prescription behind their alleged normative neutrality.

T
he interplay of the normative and the causal, or the rational and the natural, is what is at stake here. The irony is that each side appears infected by a excess of unquestioned commitment, or dogma. When the analytic naturalist endows science the authority before the real as a matter of principle, the Continentals patronizingly wave the 'positivist!' card, and with due cause. But when the so-called Marxist materialist retorts with such gnomic formulations like "there is no outside of capitalism!", the analytic rightfully scorns what appears to reduce even what telescopes allow us to see to our practice, and take it as an idealist excess. It's clear that both are victim to a kind of methodological naivete: the analytic elides the rationalist obligation to adjudicate metaphysical claims to the in-itself, and the Continental elides the ontological and epistemological levels of description in correlationism (because even science is a human practice, it is said that science cannot know of the in-itself). Pragmatism and correlationism; two sides of the same anti-realist predicament. 

a) Hegel and Marx

I think a beginning for those of us involved in 'Continental theory' is to be uncompromisingly critical with the purported materialism of Marxist philosophy. The whole Marxist 'materialist' reversal of Hegel grossly insufficient. It wants to subvert the idealism latent in Hegel's dialectics in sight of a truly materialist conception of change.  To do so, Marx naively transplants dialectical categories proper to the Concept to the material. Thus, Marx frames nature ubiquitously and historically as governed by the principle of contradiction and the law of negation. So he wants to inject negativity into the Natural to make it a dynamic force of material production and to avoid tethering it to the narrow confines Conceptual, and so to an exercise in theoretical-reason for subjective consciousness; the materiality of practice is instead set then describe how qualitative forms emerge in matter, leading to the commodity-form as a mixture of 'pure' Nature (matter) and labor, and where the latter transforms the former into the 'inorganic support' or body of man. 

This view, mostly to be found in the early Marx (1844, the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts), is still the most bluntly dialectical attempt to reconcile the becoming of the Concept with that of Matter, while not sacrificing their inextricability. But Marx's move doesn't quite work. Contradiction makes sense as a metaphysical principle to describe the dynamism of Nature if and only if one identifies logic and metaphysics, like Hegel did, because one can say that the principle of identity of indiscernibles leads to the conceptual equivalence of being and nothingness, and one can thus give blunt conceptual contradictions ontological content, from which the dialectical process takes off. One can equate conceptual indiscernibility with metaphysical identity through PII, because for idealism there is nothing in the order of being external to the identity issued by the rational Concept; the rational is what is actual. This makes sense for Hegel because you can begin with a pure abstract concept of being and have no predicative quality separate it from Nothing.

But when you want to begin from the multiplicity of Nature, before entwining with the Conceptual, it makes no sense to speak of negativity or contradiction. Marx is forced into saying ridiculous, proto-obscurantist things such as 'everything in nature has an opposite'. But what is the 'contradiction' or 'contrary' of a finger? Or of a planet? Or of a finger-part, for that matter? Marx wants the rationalist baby without the idealist bathwater, but instead ends up in methodological confusion, dislodging negativity from the Concept, where it is imbued and enveloped. Dialectical negativity cannot be transplanted into the material as an ontological motor without vitiating the rationalist coherence of the theory.

    In the end, the attempt to even say what Nature could be prior to the interplay of labor and matter becomes impossible, and the later Marx is much more bluntly descriptively empirical than 'philosophical' about Nature. The corollary of the incapacity, however, to dialectically disassociate the materiality of Nature from that of labor, the dyanmics of matter from that of production, is what allows Marxist orthodoxy to claim materialism means acknowledging that reality is determined by the dynamics of relations of production, rather than by blunt intellectual speculation. But in doing so it forgets its internal incapacity to theorize the mind-independent world of matter on which production is conditioned metaphysically. This is not going to change until the residual Hegelianism can be done away with and the theory given proper methodological footing. Otherwise, we get preposterously proto-correlationist or idealist claims like "there is no outside of capitalism!". No Marxism can survive the brutal reality of the contemporary without re-assessing its fundamental conceptual quandaries. It is clear the classical Hegelian dialectics won't do, and that negativity and contradiction/opposites are insufficient as metaphysical principles. The essential question remains: how to reconcile a rationalism with a materialism.


Of course, much Marxism has moved away and beyond the early conceptual frame that Marx inherited vis a vis Hegel (Althusser being maybe the most rigorous example). But much work still is left here; I don't think structuralism will do the trick just like that. But that is a discussion for another time.


b) Politics and Economy / Reason and Nature

Levi also mentioned, in a more recent comment:

"There are two very different types of political theory. On the one hand, there is the sort of political theory you find in thinkers like Marx, Foucault, and Deleuze and Guattari who hold that the most effective way to engage is by mapping the field of power, how it functions, its mechanisms so that people can engage better, more logistically, more strategically, more effectively. These theoristsgenerally say little about what is to be done. Their contribution is to uncover the problem.
There's another type of political theory that thinks what's important is declaring what you're against, establishing what a subject is, establishing that we have freedom or agency, and denouncing. This doesn't seem to contribute much as it seldom understands the concrete problems, how the field is organized, or how to engage. But it's fun, at least."
In response to this insightful passage, I mentioned the following points:

     I am generally suspicious of political theories that divorce diagnosis or critique from strategy. These are separate tasks, of course, but part of what probably reeks on both ends as ultimately impotent when thinking of a new possible societal organization is the saturation of descriptive-prescriptive discourse by insufficiently nuanced conceptual categories, following from an insufficient appreciation for the binding between politics and economics.

 This I find for instance in Foucault's strict historicist outlook, which is ultimately humanly sealed to the point of demoting the empirical reality of market economy. He has nothing to say about the concrete movement of economy, but plenty to say about agency, institutions, and power. I think there is some untapped 'structuralist' potential here, when dislodged from the residual humanism, however stringently Foucault's denouncing might have been against everything claiming itself to be 'human'.


I insist in that as long as theorists routinely disavow economics when doing political investigation they're repeating in a variation the nefarious move that post-Heideggerean phenomenologists-hemeneutic historicists did when routinely subordinating science to the subject, to the point of patronizing it as 'derivative abstractions' (even Habermas does this). 
All this to say: the patronizing of the intricacies of economy is the corollary of the correlationist reification of subjectivity, agency and "power". 

Now, does this mean that we must go the 'reductionist' route, and attempt to describe a political process in terms purely immanent to the material 'primacy processes'? Not quite. Recent Deleuzian-inspired accounts which follow this route face something of the opposite problem than the historicists, in that the category of agency becomes either impossible or extremely problematic, which leads into an equally impotent, and even more alienating, fetishizing of 'material process' (Nick Land anyone?). In the name of ontological univocity, and waging war against the logos of every representationalism and humanism (Deleuze included), thinkers like Land deflate the empirical-transcendental distinction to the point of effectively destroying the rational kernel in which political categories are articulated: decision, agency, obligation, all fall out the window.

These are normative categories, and as such operate within the space of reasons in which man conceives of itself through obligations and responsibilities. In destroying the autonomy of the normative, Landianism procures not just a pragmatic contradiction where all agency is dissolved, and at which point the only possible imperative is to 'intensify' the native process into which you're invariably embedded. But more fundamentally, one elides the capacity to adjudicate one's claims in rational terms, vitiating the theoretical status of one's enterprise, by destroying the logical basis of argumentation, thereby eliding the possibility of a real basis to adjudicate normative claims. It's your sci-fi counterpart to the classical romanticism of the historicists.

The resulting deficiency explains also what I take to be the brutal flaccidity of contemporary positive political visions. Without having the capacity to envision a new form of economical organization, political 'theory' is doomed to remain confined to vituperations against the State, the endless celebration of subjective and collective freedom, and the glorification of the moments of riot and demonstration. Not to demean the valence of the latter, of course. But it is clear that something like what Marx did, that is, to have a political vision sufficiently attentive to the intricacies of political economy to envelop the global scope, will need to get a grip into the concrete dynamics of the contemporary market. Without that, talk of 'relations of production' can never get off the academic conceptual commerce, which results in a placebo more than anything, encouraging the next parade of books with titles such as "The Politics of Lamentation". Romanticized historicist genealogies can do as fascinating history, and are absolutely necessary. This is not to simply identify politics with economy, but to insist that discontinuities in politics, global or local, cannot be excised from a dialectical interplay with the economic, insofar as the latter is the material support of collective organization and life. Critique of political economy is essential, and cannot be done away with.



So what is the alternative? Here I would timidly suggest that the necessary articulation between the normative and the natural is somewhat analogous to the articulation between the political and the economic. This would need some reconstructive surgery of course, but the idea, would be roughly along the following lines. We can't agree with Badiou in claiming that economy is something like the bare normality of the State, because this delivers the complex dynamics of market and the possibility of an economy to the 'fixity' of a structure, while reserving political action for the supplementary category of subjective decision, still beholden to romanticist voluntarism. It plainly divorces political subjectivation from its necessary intrication within the structural dynamics not only of a societal-state apparatus, but to a social-link determining the relations of material exchange, production and labor. Zizek criticizes the residual voluntaraism in Badiou thus as the Kantian supplement in the revolutionary's thought, somewhat justifiably. However, we must agree with Badiou and every apologist of the "free revolutionary subject", in that the economic stratum of abstract transactions and processes, or the Market, does not by itself produce wholesale structural changes, if by the latter we understand the sublation of its axiomatic efficiency.

One cannot fully dislodge the impersonal potency of market-forces from the interest of agents, and their complex social envelopment. Reducing individual and collective will to a facile moralistic Manichean distinction between the 'revolutionary elan' and the reactive capitalist 'greed', one fails to secure the proper integration of will into the pragmatics of political and economic decision, and how they make the latter not only axiomatically operational but structurally contingent. The twofold axis of rational subjective/collective decision/deliberation and the automatism of impersonal causal/axiomatic processes saturates the political and the economical in their mutual inextricability. Here, the function of critique of ideology overlaps with the making explicit of implicit norms which, inculcated by the State apparatus and the ruling class, articulate the logical nexus of the social space across a field of material inferences relaying concepts and practice,  organizing at the highest level the operational circuits of market dynamics. Ideological critique becomes of a piece with the exposing of implicit rules, challenging their normative valence. Economics here overlaps with the political, insofar as the mechanisms of deliberation proper to the latter can, once wrested from the blind efficacy of implicit norms through the use of logical and critical vocabulary, interrupt the axiomatic efficacy of the market by placing a burden of proof on the agencies that support it, and issues a challenge to its internal mechanics.

Political becoming cannot be counterposed to economic being. Being and becoming are native to economy through politics, once it is understood that the axiomatics of economy dynamize themselves by integrating decisional processes at the level of the normative. It is possible to understand discontinuities in economy without relapsing into haecceitism, while also avoiding glorifying the 'subjective revolutionary' elan at the expense of understanding the dynamics of local change. Thus, economics needs to be understood so as to explain how the dynamic processes of the market are  mobilized in interaction with the dynamics of agential processes proper to deliberation in  individuals, institutions, and so on 
(it is this intersection wherein certain concepts acquire concrete valence: share-value, risk analysis, probabilistic enveloping of financial speculation...). So what of politics then?



The possibility of structural change, in various degrees, or what I propose to call politics, concerns a possible way in which these two registers are entwined; it is not the emergence of subjectivity when the 'evental decision' disowns itself from all economic reality, breaking the latter's stasis. The Political Event cannot be dislodged from economy; we must be more Hegelian than Kantian here. Which means also, of course, more Marxist. By this I mean that in politics change is thought of in the articulation between the agential-institutional and the processual-causal at the pivotal joints, rather than in the sublation or elision of the economic in the name of the political.

But we must be more Badiouean or Sellarsian when accepting that the articulation between relations of production and the dynamics of class struggle cannot be construed in terms of a precarious concept of matter that introduces dialectical negation into it. The trick is to preserve the autonomy of political process with the natural efficacity of natural process in methodological terms, so as to avoid enveloping materiality with the conceptual (Idealism), but so as to avoid their indistinction (Land). Economy is dynamic in relating into its axiomatic aspect the agency of individuals and institutions, and subjectivity is structural in formally conditioning the dynamics of economy by virtue of being integrated into the latter's axiomatic process by the functional relaying of norms within the social space.

       The political natively related to economy is to be found at the moment not just when the former outstrips the regularity of the latter, but when it composes a dynamics of production sufficient to a set of needs, new possibilities and demands, and re-articulates the integral dynamism between the three in the form of labor and production dynamics. Demands cannot be understood outside the mediation of language and practice that informs the manifest image of man in the world, any more than it can be understood irrespective from the formal reality of value-form that inserts it into the field of commerce. But the incapacity to move outside the commodity-form which governs exchange value in capital dynamics is contingent on the present ubiquity of market-economy. Which means: any new articulation between the kernel of normativity and economics must depart from the contemporary situation. This is the only sense in which there being no outside of capitalism makes any sort of sense.

Thus, the question would be, how is it possible to have an organization of the formal reality of the economic and the materiality it supports, outside the form of the commodity? That is ultimately the task, but it cannot be resolved right away. How to have a conception of use-value adequate to the exigencies of our world outside the dynamism of generating surplus-value through the commodity form? What could such a conception of need or demand constitute, and under which practice?


Provisionally, we can muse: needs and demands are not fixed, but are partly empirically fixed by material constraints on the agents normatively articulating the social space (for example: food, health, housing...). This requires that the normative binding set the space of production-labor by developing an economic alternative to certain tasks (agriculture, medicine, construction...); or to propose the latter's axiomatization in an alternative model to market. Yet these spaces of economic reality cannot be reduced to wills that organize 'the greed of capitalist consumerism' any more than we can inflate collective action by deflating organization to 'Riot! No State!'. The latter is as powerless before Wall Street as it is when devising an effective means to organize labor so as to grow crops and distribute them across a population. We're still going to have to sink our teeth into the dynamics of market, and have the conceptual tools to devise new forms of articulation. If not, then 'bourgeois epistemology' flinging pebbles against the capitalist Iron Wall is all we have.